Important: If you reached this
web page via a link, other than to the Home page, you must go
to the Home
page to acknowledge the rules of the domain.
Back
to Unedited Philosophy Quotes and Ramblings about Intequinism.
DETAILS
OF BORROWED BOOK
Book
name: THE PASSION
OF THE WESTERN MIND. Understanding the Ideas That Have
Shaped Our World View
Author: RICHARD TARNAS
Publisher: PIMLICO (An imprint of
Random House)
Place: London, England
Date: 1996 (First published
in the USA by Crown, 1991)
After i read Sections V and VI in a borrowed
book, i purchased the book and read the other sections. The
page numbers seems to be exactly the same as in the borrowed
book. Will however type quotation from the bought book in
Arial font.
DETAILS OF BOUGHT BOOK
Book name: The Passion of the Western
Mind: Understanding the Ideas That Have Shaped Our World
View
Author:
Richard Tarnas
Publisher: Ballantine Books (First
Ballantine Books Edition: April 1993)
Place:
New York
ISBN:
0-345-36809-6
Reader: Mr. M.D. Pienaar
CONTENTS
1. What is the
essence of a copernical turn ? Illustrate this by referring
to Tarnas’ treatment of two copernical terms, and try as
well to relate this concept to Post-Modernity .
2. Give an
analysis of the use of the word “nature” in Tarnas
treatment of Modernity. How far do modern
philosophers (for instance Locke, Kant ,Rousseau,
Marx,Hannah Arendt) have
different views on of nature?
3. Describe in
your own words the main line in the lecture of Habermas
about the relationship
between Modernity and Time. What does he try to say
or to defend?
The Archetypal Forms
13
June 2013
p11
'..
a number of ambiguities and discrepancies remained
unresolved in the corpus of Plato's work. At times Plato
seems to exalt the ideal over the empirical to such an
extent that all concrete particulars are understood to be,
as it were, only a series of footnotes to the transcendent
Idea. At other times he seems to stress the intrinsic
nobility of created things, precisely because they are
embodied expressions of the divine and eternal.'
14
June 2013
P25
'Despite
the continual emergence of new problems and new attempted
solutions, a heartening sense of intellectual progress
seemed to override the various confusions accompanying it.
Thus Xenophanes could affirm: "The gods did not reveal, from
the beginning, all things to us; but in the course of time,
through seeking, men find that which is the better. …" '[1]
P26
'Pericles
himself was intimate with the rationalist philosopher and
physicist Anaxagoras, and a new intellectual rigour,
skeptical of the old supernatural explanations, was
widespread. Contemporary man now perceived himself as more a
civilized product from progress from savagery than a
degeneration from a mythical golden age.'[2]
P44
'..
at the heart of Plato's conception of the world was the
notion of a transcendent intelligence that rules and orders
all things: divine Reason is "the king of heaven and earth."
'
p44-45
'Plato
also
recognized in the world's composition and irreducible
element of stubborn errancy and irrationality, which he
referred to as anankē,
or Necessity. In the Platonic understanding, the
irrational was associated with matter, with the sensible
world, and with the instinctual desire, while the rational
was associated with mind, with the transcendent, and with
spiritual desire.'[3]
P45
'Yet
precisely because of its problematic nature, anankē serves as
an impulsion for the philosopher's ascent from the visible
to the transcendent.'
Self
'..
from the visible to the transcendent.' above implies my
thoughts that true transcendence is dependent on having
realities in minds after societal honesties and true
pre-knowledge. This is how i understood Plato's philosophy
whilst studying PHIL221 (History of philosophy) and reading
the Republic, especially the comparison of the Good and the
Sun and the distinction between true knowledge, knowledge
and opinion.
20
June 2013
P101
'The
correspondence between this conception of Christ and that of
the Greek Logos did not go unnoticed by Hellenistic
Christians. The remarkable Hellenistic Jewish philosopher
Philo of Alexandria, an older contemporary of Jesus and
Paul, had already broached a Judaic-Greek synthesis pivoted
on the term "Logos."[4]
But it was with the opening words of the Gospel according to
John, "In the beginning was the Logos," that Christianity's
relationship to Hellenic philosophy was potently initiated.
Soon afterward, an extraordinary convergence of Greek
thought and Christian theology was in progress that would
leave both transformed.'
P102
'In
their understanding of Christ as the incarnate Logos, early
Christian theologians synthesized the Greek philosophical
doctrine of the intelligible divine rationality of the world
with the Judaic religious doctrine of the creative Word of
God, which manifested a personal God's providential will and
gave to human history its salvational meaning. In Christ the
Logos became man: the historical and the timeless, the
absolute and the personal, the human and the divine became
one.'
P105
'
"And the Logos became flesh and dwelt among us." '
p114
'Despite
his
erudition and appreciation for the intellectual and
scientific achievements of the Greeks, Augustine proclaimed:
"… It is enough for the Christian to believe that the only
cause of all created things, whether heavenly or earthly,
whether visible or invisible, is the goodness of the
Creator, the one true God; and that nothing exists but
Himself that does not derive its existence from Him." '[5]
P103
'As
Clement of Alexandria announced, "By the Logos, the whole
world is now become Athens and Greece." '
21
June 2013
P179
Whilst
reading
about Thomas Aquinas i thought Tarnas implied the following:
Thomas Aquinas drew a comparison between reality and what is
in a person's mind and that the more equal the two are the
more likely is beatification. I looked for it in the section
of Aquinas but did not find it there.
P191
P196
P91-197
Christian
philosophy digressed from rational Platonic views to
empiricist Aristotelian views during the period from Jesus's
life to the time of Meister Eckhart, when especially in the
Rhineland a return to rationalism occurred.
P198
'The
life of Christ and the apostles was acknowledged as the
paradigm of spiritual existence, but that life appeared to
be neither represented nor mediated by the contemporary
structures of the Catholic Church. And the new spiritual
autonomy embraced by the Rhineland mystics, as well as by
others in England and the Low Countries, tended to place the
Church in a secondary role in the realm of authentic
spirituality.'
P201
'..
in the fourteenth century in the paradoxical figure of
William of Ockham .. A British philosopher and priest born
soon after Aquinas's death ..'
p202
'Human
concepts possessed no metaphysical foundation beyond
concrete particulars, and there existed no necessary
correspondence between words and things. Ockham thereby gave
new force and vitality to the philosophical position of
nominalism (in its conceptualist version), which held that
universals were only names or mental concepts and not real
entities.'
p203
'A
separate, independent order of reality populated by
universals or Forms was expressly denied. Ockham thus moved
to eliminate the last vestige of Platonic Forms in
Scholastic thought: Only the particular existed, and any
inference about real universals, whether transcendent or
immanent, was spurious. So often and with such force did
Ockham use the philosophical principle that "entities are
not to be multiplied beyond necessity" (non sunt multiplicanda
entia praeter necessitate)' that the principle came to
be known as "Ockham's razor."[6]
Hence, according to Ockham, universals exist only in
the human mind, not in reality. They are concepts abstracted
by the mind on the basis of its empirical observations of
more or less similar individuals. They are not God's
pre-existing Ideas governing his creation of individuals,
for God was absolutely free to create anything in any way he [own italics]
pleased. Only his
[own italics] creatures exist, not Ideas of creatures. For
Ockham, the issue was no longer the metaphysical question as
to how ephemeral individuals came from real transcendent
Forms, but the epistemological question as to how abstract
universal concepts came from real individuals. "Man" as a
species signified not a distinct real entity in itself, but
shared similarity in many individual human beings as
recognized by the mind. It was a mental abstraction, not a
real entity. The problem of universals was therefore a
matter of epistemology, grammar, and logic—not of
metaphysics or ontology.
Ockham, again following leads
established by Scotus, also denied the possibility of moving
from a rational apprehension of the facts of this world to
any necessary conclusions about God or other religious
matters.'
Self
The
above proves that empiricism and nominalism took hold in
Britain and rationalism particularly in the Rhineland. When
Tarnas and/or Ockham refer to 'in the human mind' as not
reality, it implies that a real issue exists with regards to
the nature of thoughts. To me a thought is reality because
according to Descartes "cogito ergo sum" a thought is the
most immanent thing, which a person cannot doubt. The
deterministic effect of thoughts cannot be doubted because
in a rational sense, idealism implies that after all
materialist deterministic factors have been overcome,
thoughts, which caused the overcoming is still
deterministic.
P206-207
'In
Ockham's view, one could not assume that man's mind and
God's were fundamentally connected. Empiricism and reason
could give a limited knowledge of the world in its
particulars, but no certain knowledge of God, for which only
God's Word could be a source. Revelation offered certainty,
but could be affirmed only through faith and grace, not
<p207> through natural reason.'
⌘⌘⌘
p208
'And
so it was that just as the medieval vision had attained its
consummation in the work of Aquinas and Dante, the
altogether different spirit of a new epoch began to arise,
propelled by the very forces that had achieved the earlier
synthesis. The great medieval masterworks had culminated an
intellectual development that was starting to break into new
territories, even if that meant stepping out of the Church's
established structure of education and belief. But Ockham's
precocious modernism was still ahead of its time.
Paradoxically, the culture of this new era would receive its
major initiating impulse not from the line of medieval
Scholasticism, natural science, and Aristotle, but from the
other pole of classical Humanism, belles lettres, and a
revived Plato. For just as Aquinas had his contrasting
philosophical successor in Ockham, so did Dante have his
contrasting literary successor in Petrarch, born in the same
decade Dante began writing La Divina Commedia,
at the start of the fourteenth century.'
P209-211
It
seems Petrarch was a romantic.
P211
'It
was this new self-reflective awareness of human life's
richness and multidimensionality, and his recognition of a
kindred spirit in the great writers of antiquity, that made
Petrarch the first man of the Renaissance.'
P213
'With
the
universities trapped in a backwater of intellectual
orthodoxy, a Platonic Academy was founded in Florence in the
second half of the fifteenth century, under the patronage of
Cosimo de Medici and the leadership of Ficino, and this
became the flourishing center of the Platonic revival.
In
Platonism and Neoplatonism the Humanists discovered a
non-Christian spiritual tradition possessing a religious and
ethical profundity seemingly comparable to that of
Christianity itself.'
P214-215
'In
1486, at the age of twenty-three, Pico announced his
intention to defned nine hundred theses derived from various
Greek, Latin, Hebrew, and Arabic writers, invited scholars
from all over Europe to Rome for a public disputation, and
composed for the event his celebrated Oration on the Dignity
of Man. In it Pico described the Creation using both
Genesis and the Timaeus as initial sources, but then went
further: When God had completed the creation of the world as
a sacred temple of his
[own italics] divine wisdom, he [own italics] at last considered the
creation of man, whose role would be to reflect on, admire,
and love the immense grandeur of God's work. But God found he [own italics]
had no archetypes remaining with which to make man, and he [own italics]
therefore said to his
[own italics] last creation:
"Neither
an established place, nor a form belonging to you alone, nor
any special function have We [own italics] given to you, O Adam, and for
<p215> this reason, that you may have and possess,
according to your desire and judgment, whatever place,
whatever form, and whatever functions you shall desire. The
nature of other creatures, which has been determined, is
confined within the bounds prescribed by Us [own italics].
You, who are confined by no limits, shall determine for
yourself your own nature, in accordance with your own free
will, in whose hand I
[own italics] have placed you. I [own italics]
have set you at the center of the world, so that from there
you may more easily survey whatever is in the world. We have
made you neither heavenly nor earthly, neither mortal nor
immortal, so that, more freely and more honorably the molder
and maker of yourself, you may fashion yourself in whatever
form you shall prefer. You shall be able to descend among
the lower forms of being, which are brute beasts; you shall
be able to be reborn out of judgment of your own soul into
the higher beings, which are divine."[7]
P217-218
'Equally
uncongenial to the conservative theologians was the
Neoplatonic belief in the uncreated divine spark in man,
whereby divine genius could overtake the human personality
and exalt man to the summits of spiritual illumination and
creative power. While this conception, as well as the
ancient polytheistic mythologies, provided a foundational
and stimulus for the emerging Renaissance artistic genius
(Michelangelo, for example, was Ficino's student in
Florence), it also undercut the Church's traditional
limitation of divinity to God alone and to the sacramental
institutions of the Church. The elevation of man to a
God-like status, as described by Ficino and Pico, seemed to
contravene the more strictly defined orthodox Christian
dichotomy between Creator and creature, and the Doctrine of
the Fall. Pico's statement in the Oratio to the
effect that man could freely determine his being at any
level of the cosmos, including union with God, without any
mention of a mediating savior, could easily be interpreted
as a heretical breach of the established sacred hierarchy.
It
is not surprising, then, that a papal commission condemned
several of Pico's propositions, or that the pope forbade the
international public assembly Pico had planned. Yet the
Church hierarchy in Rome largely tolerated and even embraced
the classical revival, especially as men like the Florentine
Medici made their way into papal power and began using
Church resources to underwrite the enormous artistic
masterworks of the Renaissance (establishing indulgences,
for example, to help pay for <p218> them).'
P218
'The
new religious sensibility of the Humanists revitalized the
spiritual life of Western culture just as it was decaying
under the secularization of the Church and the extreme
rationalism of the late medieval universities. …
…
The Humanists anti-Aristotelianism strengthened the
culture's movement toward intellectual independence from the
increasingly dogmatic authority of the Aristotelian
tradition dominating the universities.'
Self
Tarnas's
use of the word rationalism is not certain. In sections V
and VI he used rationalism as the opposite of empiricism.
Above he writes of 'extreme rationalism' in the late
medieval universities. I currently perceive the late
medieval universities to have been highly empirical in their
thought processes, which were then changed by Platonic
rationalism at the beginning of the modern era or the end of
the Middle Age.
29 April 2013
“Within the span
of a single generation, Leonardo, Michelangelo, and Raphael
produced their masterworks. Columbus discovered the New
World, Luther rebelled against the Catholic Church and began
the Reformation, and Copernicus hypothesized a heliocentric
universe and commenced the Scientific Revolution. … Man was
now capable of … He could defy traditional authorities and
assert a truth based on his own judgement. … Pico’s
proclamation of man’s dignity seemed fulfilled.”
“..
mid-fourteenth century, the black plague swept through
Europe and destroyed a third of the continent’s population,
fatally undermining the balance of economic and cultural
elements that had sustained the high medieval civilization.
Many believed that the wrath of God had come upon the world.
… The universities were sclerotic.”
“Ecclesiastical
conspiracies were routine, and included such events as a
papally backed assassination in front of the Florentine
cathedral altar at High Mass on Easter Sunday. … the Church
itself, the West’s fundamental cultural institution, seemed
to many the very center of decadent corruption, its
structure and purpose devoid of spiritual integrity.”
“As with the
medieval cultural revolution several centuries earlier.
Technical inventions played a pivotal role in the making of
the new era. Four in particular (all with Oriental
precursors) had been brought into widespread use in the West
by this time, with immense cultural ramifications: the
magnetic compass, which permitted the navigational feats
that opened the globe to European exploration; gunpowder,
which contributed to the demise of the old feudal order and
the ascent of nationalism; the mechanical clock, which
brought about a decisive change in the human relationship to
time, nature, and work, .. and the printing press, ..
<p226> eroded the monopoly on learning long held by
the clergy.”
“Moreover, the
spread of the printed word and growing literacy contributed
to a new cultural ethos marked by increasingly individual
and private, noncommunal forms of communication and
experience, thereby encouraging the growth of individualism.
Silent reading and solitary reflection helped free the
individual ways of thinking, and from collective control of
thinking, with individual readers now having private access
to a multiplicity of other perspectives and forms of
experience.”
“.. came also
the encounter with new cultures, religions, and ways of
life, introducing into the European awareness a new spirit
of skeptical relativism concerning the absoluteness of its
own traditional assumptions.”
“The Italian
city-states of the fourteenth and fifteenth
centuries—Florence, Milan, Venice, Urbino, and others—were
in many ways the most advanced urban centers in Europe. ..
continual contact with the older civilizations of the East
presented them with an unusually concentrated inflow of
economic and cultural wealth. … The Italian city-states’
small size, their independence from externally sanctioned
authority, and their commercial and cultural vitality all
provided a political stage upon which a new spirit of bold,
creative, and often ruthless individualism could flourish.”
“So too did
Copernicus and Kepler, with Neoplatonic and Pythagorean
motivations, seek solutions to problems in astronomy that
would satisfy aesthetic imperatives, a strategy which led
them to the heliocentric <p231> universe. No less
significant was the strong religious motivation, usually
combined with Platonic themes, impelling most of the major
figures in the Scientific Revolution through Newton. For
implicit in all these activities was the half-inarticulate
notion of a distant mythical golden age when all things had
been known—the Garden of Eden, ancient classical times, a
past era of great sages. Mankind’s fall from this primal
state of enlightenment and grace had brought about a drastic
loss of knowledge. Recovery of knowledge was therefore
endowed with religious significance.”
“But when all
these “causes” of the Renaissance have been enumerated, one
still senses that the essential thrust of the Renaissance
was something larger than any of these factors, than all of
them combined. Instead, the historical record suggests there
was concurrently on many fronts an emphatic emergence of a
new consciousness—..—and that this emergence had its own
raison d’être, was propelled by some greater and more
subsuming force than any combination of political, social,
technological, religious, philosophical, or artistic
factors. …: history was perceived and defined for the first
time as a tripartite structure—ancient, medieval,
modern—thus sharply differentiating the classical and
medieval eras, with the Renaissance itself at the vanguard
of the new age. <p232> More than “causes” were
operative here. A spontaneous and irreducible revolution of
consciousness was taking place, affecting virtually every
aspect of Western culture.”
Reader currently
postulate that the main reason for the changes was objective
communication and spread of knowledge, combined with
courageous honesties due to new faiths that made honest
courageous communications possible against the forces, which
undermines corresponding communications.
“It was when the
spirit of Renaissance individualism reached the realm of
theology and religious conviction within the Church, in the
person of the German Augustinian monk Martin Luther, that
there erupted in Europe the momentous Protestant
Reformation.”
“The relaxed
cultural syncretism displayed by the Renaissance Church’s
embrace of Greco-Roman pagan culture (including the immense
expense of patronage this embrace demanded) helped
precipitate the collapse of the Church’s absolute religious
authority.”
“The proximate
cause of the Reformation was the papacy’s attempt to finance
the architectural and artistic glories of the High
Renaissance by the theologically dubious means of selling
spiritual indulgences. Tetzel, the traveling friar whose
sale of indulgences in Germany provoked Luther in 1517 to
post his Ninety-five Theses, had been so authorized by the
Medici Pope Leo X to raise money for building Saint Peter’s
Basilica. An indulgence was the remission of punishment for
a sin after guilt had been sacramentally forgiven—a Church
practice influenced by the pre-Christian Germanic custom of
commuting the physical penalty for a crime to a money
payment. … raise money for financing crusades and building
cathedrals and hospitals. At first applied only to penalties
imposed by the Church in this life, by Luther’s time
indulgences were being granted to remit penalties imposed by
God in the afterlife, including immediate release from
purgatory.”
The intequities
values were thus in the new ideas of construction and
medicine, for which the church raised money.
‘Yet
the more immediate cause, the Church’s expensive patronage
of high culture, does illuminate a deeper factor behind the
Reformation—namely, the anti-Hellenic spirit with which
Luther sought to purify Christianity and return it to its
pristine biblical foundation. For
the Reformation was not least a purist “Judaic” reaction
against the Hellenic (and Roman) impulse of Renaissance
culture, of Scholastic philosophy, and of much postapostolic
Christianity in general.’
“It
was finally, the faith in God’s redeeming power as revealed
through Christ in the Bible, and that alone, which rendered
Luther’s experience of salvation, and upon that exclusive
rock he built his new church of a reformed Christianity.”
“..:
Justification occurred by faith alone. The Christian
believer had to be liberated from the obscuring clutches of
the old system, for only by being directly responsible to
God could he be free to experience God’s grace. The only
source of theological authority now lay in the literal
meaning of Scripture.”
20 May 2013
p.237
‘In
the Protestant vision, true Christianity was founded on
“faith alone,” “grace alone,” and “Scripture alone.” …
Erasmus also argued against Luther that man’s free will and
virtuous actions were not to be entirely discounted as
elements in the process of salvation. Catholicism held that
divine grace and human merit were both instrumental in
redemption and did not have to be viewed in opposition, with
exclusively one or the other operative. … The Protestant
spirit prevailed in half of Europe, and the old order was
broken. Western Christianity was no longer exclusively
Catholic, nor monolithic, nor a source of cultural unity.’
p.238
‘While
Protestantism was optimistic concerning God, the
gratuitously merciful preserver of the elect, it was
uncompromisingly pessimistic concerning man, that “teeming
horde of infamies” (Calvin). Human freedom was so bound to
evil that it consisted merely in the ability to choose among
different degrees of sin.’
p.239
‘In the
Protestant vision, neither the pope nor the Church councils
possessed the spiritual competence to define Christian
belief. Luther taught instead the “priesthood of all
believers”: religious authority rested finally and solely in
each individual Christian, reading and interpreting the
Bible according to his own private conscience in the context
of his personal relationship to God.’
‘Luther’s
impassioned words before the imperial Diet declared a new
manifesto of personal religious freedom: “Unless I am
convinced by Scripture and plain reason—I do not accept the
authority of popes and councils, for they have contradicted
each other—my conscience is captive to the Word of God. I
cannot and I will not recant anything, for to go against
conscience is neither right nor safe. God help me. Amen.”
p.241
‘By
disenchanting the world of immanent divinity, completing the
process initiated by Christianity’s destruction of pagan
animism, the Reformation better allowed for its radical
revision by modern science. The way was then clear for an
increasingly naturalistic view of the cosmos, moving first
to the remote rationalist Creator of Deism, and finally to
secular agnosticism’s elimination of any supernatural
reality.
p.243
‘Truth
increasingly became truth-as-experienced-by-the-self. Thus
the road opened by Luther would move through Pietism to
Kantian critical philosophy and Romantic philosophical
idealism to, finally, the philosophical pragmatism and
existentialism of the late modern era.’
p.246-247
‘But the
Counter-Reformation was spearheaded above all by the
Jesuits, a Roma Catholic order that established itself as
militantly loyal to the pope and attracted a considerable
number of strong-willed and intellectually sophisticated
men. …
<p.247>
The classical humanistic tradition based on the Greek paideia was thereby
broadly sustained during the following two centuries,
offering the growing educated class of Europeans a new
source of cultural unity just as the old source,
Christianity, was fragmenting. … It was no accident that
Galileo and Descartes, Voltaire and Diderot all received
Jesuit educations.’
p.248
‘Born in Poland
and educated in Italy, Copernicus lived during the height of
the Renaissance. Though it was destined to become an
unquestioned principle of existence for the modern psyche,
the central tenet of his vision was inconceivable to most
Europeans in his own lifetime. More than any other single
factor, it was the Copernican insight that provoked and
symbolized the drastic, fundamental break from the ancient
and medieval universe to that of the modern era.’
… how
to explain the apparently erratic planetary movements by
means of a simple, clear, elegant formula. To recapitulate,
the solutions proposed by Ptolemy and all his successors,
solutions based on the geocentric Aristotelian cosmos, had
required the employment of increasingly numerous
mathematical devices—deferents, major and minor epicycles,
equants, eccentrics—in the attempt to make sense ... Further
discrepancies were solved by compounding the circles,
displacing the centers, positing yet another center from
which motion remained uniform, and so on.
p.249-250
‘Renaissance
Europe urgently needed a better calendar, and the Church,
for which the calendar was indispensable in administrative
and liturgical matters, undertook its reform. Such reform
depended on astronomical precision. Copernicus, asked to
advise the papacy on the problem, ... He found that
several Greek philosophers, notably of Pythagorean and
Platonist background, had proposed a moving Earth,
although none had developed the hypothesis to its full
astronomical and mathematical conclusions. Hence
Aristotle’s geocentric conception had not been the only
judgment of the <p.250> revered Greek authorities.
.. Neoplatonists’ exalted conception of the Sun, .. ,
Copernicus hypothesized a Sun-centered universe with a
planetary Earth and mathematically worked out the
implications. … The heliocentric model readily explained
the apparent daily movement of the heavens and annual
motion of the Sun as due to the Earth’s daily rotation on
its axis and its annual revolution around the central Sun.
The appearance of the moving Sun and stars could now be
recognized as deceptively created by the Earth’s own
movements.’
p.251
‘Having
set down a first version of his thesis in a short
manuscript, the Commentariolus,
Copernicus circulated it among his friends as early as 1514.
Two decades later, a lecture on the principles of his new
system was given in Rome before the pope, who approved. …
But as a few proficient astronomers began to find
Copernicus’s argument persuasive, the opposition began to
mount; and it was the religious implications of the new
cosmology that quickly provoked the most intense attacks.’
p.251
‘In
the beginning, that opposition did not come from the
Catholic Church. Copernicus was a canon in good standing a
Catholic cathedral and an esteemed consultant to the Church
in Rome.’
p.252
‘By
tolerating and even encouraging the exploration of Greek
philosophy, science, and secular thinking, including the
Hellenistic metaphorical interpretation of Scripture, the
Church had, in Protestant eyes, allowed pristine
Christianity and the literal truth of the Bible to be
contaminated. .. the Copernican hypothesis contradicted
several passages in the Holy Scripture concerning the fixity
of the Earth, and Scripture was Protestantism’s one absolute authority. … When Rheticus
took Copernicus’s manuscript to Nürnberg to be published,
he was forced by reformers’ opposition to go elsewhere. …
…
And by Galileo’s time in the early seventeenth century, the
Catholic Church—now with a renewed sense of the need for
doctrinal orthodoxy—felt compelled to take a definite stand
against the Copernican hypothesis. While in an earlier
century, Aquinas or the ancient Church fathers might have
readily considered a metaphorical interpretation of the
scriptural passages in question, thereby eliminating the
apparent contradiction with science, the emphatic literalism
of Luther and his followers had activated a similar attitude
in the Catholic Church.’
p.253-254
‘..
astronomer Giordano Bruno. Bruno had widely promulgated an
advanced version of the heliocentric theory … Certainly the
fact that the same man [Bruno: own insert] who held
heretical views on the Trinity and other vital theological
matters had also taught the Copernican theory .. After Bruno
was burned at the stake in 1600 (though not for his
heliocentric teachings), Copernicanism seemed a more
dangerous theory—both to religious authorities and to
philosopher-astronomers, each for their different reasons.
…
The essential dichotomy between the celestial and
terrestrial realms, the great cosmological structure of
Heaven, Hell, and Purgatory, the circling planetary spheres
with angelic hosts, God’s empyrean throne above all, the
moral drama of human life pivotally centered between
spiritual heavens and corporeal Earth—all would be cast into
question or destroyed altogether by the new theory. … If the
Earth truly moved, then no longer could it be the fixed
center of God’s Creation and his plan of salvation. Nor
could man be the central focus of the cosmos. The absolute
uniqueness and significance of Christ’s intervention into
human history seemed to require a corresponding
<p.254> uniqueness and significance for the Earth. …
Catholic Church .. condemned in no uncertain terms the
heliocentric hypothesis. .. Galileo interrogated by the
Inquisition, forced to recant and placed under house arrest
.. all teachings and writings upholding the motion of the
Earth prohibited. With the Copernican theory, Catholicism’s
long-held tension between reason and faith had finally
snapped.’
p.255
‘And
he [Copernicus: own insert] had not adequately answered
obvious physical objections to a moving Earth, such as why
terrestrial objects would not simply fall off the Earth as
it swept through space.
Despite
the radical quality of the Copernican hypothesis, a
planetary Earth was the only major innovation in the De Revolutionibus,
a work that was otherwise solidly within the ancient and
medieval astronomical tradition. Copernicus had caused the
first break from the old cosmology, and thereby created all
the problems to be solved by Kepler, Galileo, Descartes, and
Newton before they could offer a comprehensive scientific
theory capable of integrating a planetary Earth. … It was
above all not utilitarian scientific accuracy but aesthetic
superiority that would attract those crucial supporters to
the Copernican cause. …
For
Kepler, with his passionate belief in the transcendent power
of numbers and geometrical forms, his vision of the Sun as
the central image of the Godhead, and his devotion to the
celestial “harmony of the spheres,” was yet more impelled by
Neoplatonic motivations than Copernicus.’
p.256-257
‘Kepler
.. Tycho de Brahe, his [Kepler: own insert] predecessor as
imperial mathematician and astrologer to the Holy Roman
Emperor. (1) …
...
Kepler at last discovered that the observations precisely
matched orbits shaped as ellipses, with the Sun as one of
the two foci, .. –fastest near the Sun, slowest away from
the Sun, with equal areas swept out in equal times. …
Thus
Kepler at last solved the ancient problem of the planets and
fulfilled Plato’s extraordinary prediction of single,
uniform, mathematically ordered orbits—and in so doing
vindicated the Copernican hypothesis. With elliptical orbits
replacing the Ptolemaic circles, and with the <p.257>
law of equal areas replacing that of equal arcs, …
overarching principles which gave convincing evidence that
the universe was arranged with elegant mathematical
harmonies. … conclusions affirmed both Copernicus’s theory
and the mathematical mysticism of the ancient Pythagorean
and Platonic philosophers.’
p.258
‘..
Pythagorean claim for mathematics as the key .. thereby
revealing the previously hidden grandeur of God’s creation.’
p.258
‘But
coincidentally, in 1609, the same year that Kepler published
in Prague his laws of planetary motion, Galileo in Padua
turned his recently constructed telescope to the heavens ..
his observations—the craters .. stars of the Milky Way—was
interpreted by Galileo as powerful evidence in favor of the
Copernican heliocentric theory.
If
the Moon’s surface was uneven, like the Erath’s, and if the
Sun had spots that came and went, then these bodies were not
the perfect, incorruptible, and immutable celestial objects
of Aristotelian-Ptolemaic cosmology.’
p.259
‘A
new celestial world was opening up to the Western mind, just
as a new terrestrial world was being opened by the global
explorers.’
p.262
…
…
Influenced as always by the Neoplatonic exaltation of the
Sun, he [Kepler: own insert] believed the Sun to be an
active source of movement in the universe. … Kepler thereby
made the first proposal that the planets in their orbits
were moved by mechanical forces, ..’
p.263
‘To combat the
Aristotelians, Galileo developed both a new procedure for
analyzing phenomena and a new basis for testing theories. He
argued that to make accurate judgments concerning nature,
scientists should consider only precisely measurable
“objective” qualities (size, shape, number, weight, motion),
while merely perceptible qualities (color, sound, taste,
touch, smell) should be ignored as subjective and ephemeral.
… In addition, while Aristotle’s empiricism had been
predominantly a descriptive and, especially as exaggerated
by later Aristotelians, logico-verbal approach, Galileo now
established the quantitative experiment as the final test of
hypotheses. Finally, to further penetrate nature’s
mathematical regularities and true character, Galileo
employed, developed, or invented a host of technical
instruments—lens, telescope, microscope, geometric compass,
magnet, air thermometer, hydrostatic balance. The use of
such instruments gave a new dimension to empiricism unknown
to the Greeks, a dimension that undercut both the theories
and the practice of the Aristotelian professors.’
p.264
‘Galileo
analyzed projectile motion and developed the crucial idea of
inertia. … Force was required to explain only change in
motion, not constant motion. … Through this concept of
inertia, however, Galileo demonstrated that a moving Earth
would automatically endow all its objects and projectiles
with the Earth’s own motion, and therefore the collective
inertial motion would be imperceptible to anyone on the
Earth.
In
the course of his life’s work, Galileo had effectively
supported the Copernican theory, initiated the full
mathematization of nature, grasped the idea of force as a
mechanical agent, laid the foundations of modern mechanics
and experimental physics, and developed the working
principles of modern scientific method.’
p.264-265
'Because Galileo had missed the significance of
the planetary laws discovered by his contemporary Kepler, he
had continued to maintain the traditional understanding of
celestial <p.265> motion as circular orbits, only now
centered around the Sun.'
p.265-266
Atomism of
Democritus and his colleagues fit in with the neo-platonic
view of a planetary Earth because atomism also had no center
for their universe. The Aristotelian centered Earth implied
a finite universe because an infinite universe can have no
center.
p.266
‘The esoteric
philosopher-scientist Bruno was the first to perceive the
congruence between the two systems.'
p.267
‘The basic
principles of ancient atomism offered may parallels to
Descartes’s image of nature as an intricate impersonal
machine strictly ordered by mathematical law. Like
Democritus, Descartes assumed that the physical world was
composed of an infinite number of particles, or
“corpuscles,” which mechanically collided and aggregated. As
a Christian, however, he assumed that these corpuscles did
not move in utterly random fashion, but obeyed certain laws
imposed on them by a providential God at their creation.’
p.268
‘.. the inertial
motion of the planets, including that of the Earth, would
necessarily tend to propel them in a tangential straight
line away from the curving orbit around the Sun. Since,
however, their orbits were maintained in continuous closed
curves without such centrifugal breaks, it was evident that
some factor was forcing the planets toward the Sun—or as
Descartes and his successors more revealingly formulated it,
something was continually forcing the planets to “fall”
toward the Sun. … The fact that the planets moved at all was
now explicable by inertia. But the form that motion took—the
planets’ constant maintenance of elliptical orbits about the
Sun—still demanded explanation. … Thus two fundamental
questions remained, one celestial and one terrestrial: Given
inertia, why did the Earth and other planets continually
fall towards the Sun? And given a moving noncentral Earth,
why did terrestrial objects fall to the Earth at all?”
p.269
‘The notion of
an attractive force acting between all material bodies had
also been developing. Among the Greeks, Empedocles had
posited such a force. … By the third quarter of the
seventeenth century, Robert Hooke had clearly glimpsed the
synthesis: that a single attractive force governed both
planetary motions and falling bodies. Moreover, he
mechanically demonstrated his idea with a pendulum swung in
an elongated circular path, its linear motion being
continuously deflected by a central attraction. …
It
finally fell to Isaac Newton, born on Christmas Day the year
of Galileo’s death, to complete the Copernican revolution by
quantitatively establishing gravity as a universal force—a
force that could simultaneously cause both the fall of
stones to the Earth and the closed orbits of the planets
around the Sun.
p.270
‘Every particle
of matter in the universe attracted every other particle
with a force proportional to the product of their masses and
inversely proportional to the square of the distance between
them.
…
Through the concept of a quantitatively defined attractive
force, he had integrated the two major themes of
seventeenth-century science—the mechanistic philosophy and
the Pythagorean tradition. … Newton had revealed the true
nature of reality: Voltaire called him the greatest man who
ever lived.’
p.271
‘In this
universe, the Earth moved about the Sun, which was one star
among a multitude, just as the Earth was one planet among
many, and neither Sun nor Earth was at the center of the
universe.
… It
also seemed reasonable to assume that after the creation of
this intricate and orderly universe, God removed himself
from further active involvement or intervention in nature,
and allowed it to run on its own according to these perfect,
immutable laws. The new image of the Creator was thus that
of a divine architect, a master mathematician and clock
maker, while the universe was viewed as a uniformly
regulated and fundamentally impersonal phenomenon. … One
could scarcely doubt that man was the crown of creation. The
Scientific Revolution—and the birth of the modern era—was
now complete.’
21 May 2013
p.273
‘While Socrates
had equated knowledge with virtue, Bacon equated knowledge
with power. Its practical usefulness was the very measure of
its validity. With Bacon, science took on a new
role—utilitarian, utopian, the material and human
counterpart to God’s plan of spiritual salvation. … The
pursuit of natural science was therefore his religious
obligation. …
… No
longer should the pursuer of knowledge start from abstract
definitions and verbal distinctions and then reason
deductively, forcing the phenomena into prearranged order.
Instead, he must begin with the unbiased analysis of
concrete data and only then reason inductively, and
cautiously, to reach general, empirically supported
conclusions.’
p.274
‘The mind must
humble itself, rein itself in. Otherwise science would be
impossible.’
…
Only by recognizing the distinction between God and his
creation, and between God’s mind and man’s, could man
achieve real progress in science. Thus Bacon expressed the
spirit of the Reformation and of Ockham. …
Because
all the previous systems of philosophy from the Greeks
onward lacked a rigorously critical sense-based empiricism,
because they relied on rational and imaginative construction
unsupported by careful experiment, they were like grandly
entertaining theatrical productions, of no genuine relevance
to the real world they so elegantly distorted.’
p.275
‘With Bacon was
evident the modern turning of the tide in philosophy. The
nominalism and empiricism of the later Scholastics, and
their growing criticism of Aristotle and speculative
theology, now found bold and influential expression. It is true
that for all his shrewdness, Bacon drastically
underestimated the power of mathematics for the
development of the new natural science, he failed to grasp
the necessity of theoretical conjecture prior to empirical
observation, and he altogether missed the significance of
the new heliocentric theory.’
p.275
‘If
it was Bacon in England who helped inspire the distinctive
character, direction, and vigor of the new science, it was
Descartes on the Continent who established its philosophical
foundation, and in so doing articulated the epochal defining
statement of the modern self.’
p.276
‘A skeptical
crisis in French philosophy had emerged, a crisis that the
young Descartes, steeped in the critical rationalism of his
Jesuit schooling, experienced acutely.’
p.277-278
‘For in the
process of methodical doubting everything, even the apparent
reality of the physical world and his own body (which could
all be only a dream), Descartes concluded that there was one
datum that could not be doubted—the fact of his own
doubting. At least the “I” who is conscious of doubting, the
thinking subject, exists. At least this much is certain: Cogito, ergo sum—I
think, therefore I am. All else can be questioned, but not
the irreducible fact of the thinker’s self-awareness. …
The cogito was thus
the first principle and paradigm of all other knowledge,
providing both a basis for subsequent deductions and a model
for all other self-evident rational intuitions. From the
indubitable existence of the doubting subject, which was
ipso facto an awareness of imperfection and limitation,
Descartes deduced the necessary existence of a perfect
infinite being, God. … Only through presupposition of such a
God could the reliability of the natural light of human
reason, or the objective reality of the phenomenal world, be
assured. For if God is God, which is to say a perfect being,
then he would not deceive man and the reason that gives man
self-evident truths.
…
only as object. Thus res
cogitans—thinking substance, subjective experience,
spirit, consciousness, that which man perceives as
within—was understood as fundamentally different and
separate from res
extensa—extended substance, the objective world,
matter, the physical body, plants and animals, stones and
stars, the entire physical universe, everything
<p.278> that man perceives as outside his mind. Only
in man did the two realities come together as mind and body.
And
both the cognitive capacity of human reason and the
objective reality and order of the natural world found
their common source in God.’
⌘⌘⌘
p.280
‘Thus Bacon and
Descartes—prophets of a scientific civilization, rebels
against an ignorant past, and zealous students of
nature—proclaimed the twin epistemological bases of the
modern mind. In their respective manifestos of empiricism
and rationalism, the long-growing significance of the
natural world and the human reason, initiated by the Greeks
and recovered by the Scholastics, achieved definitive modern
expression. Upon this dual foundation, philosophy proceeded
and science triumphed: It was not accidental to Newton’s
accomplishment that he had systematically employed a
practical synthesis of Bacon’s inductive empiricism and
Descartes’s deductive mathematical rationalism, thereby
bringing to fruition the scientific method first forged by
Galileo.’
p.283
‘And
so between the fifteenth and seventeenth centuries, the West
saw the emergence of a newly self-conscious and autonomous
human being—curious about the world, .. responsible for his
own beliefs and actions, .. and all together less dependent
on an omnipotent God.’ … Out of that profound cultural
transformation, science emerged as the West’s new faith.’
The
above shows the misunderstandings about the faiths of
Descartes relating to truths and honesties. With the
sceptics’ probable techniques of instilling fear, Descartes
must have had a lot of faith to form his work and stay
honest and not fall prey to the sceptics’ probable attempts
to change his faith, which was most probably his salvation.
p.283
‘..
the most astonishing global shift of all had now dawned on
the cultural psyche: the Earth moves. The straightforward
evidence of the naive senses, the theological and scientific
certitude of the naive centuries, that the Sun rises and
sets and that the Earth beneath one’s feet is utterly
stationary at the center of the universe, was now overcome
through critical reasoning, mathematical calculation, and
technologically enhanced observation.’
p.287-288
‘While
the cosmology of the classical era was geocentric, finite,
and hierarchical, with the surrounding heavens the locus of
transcendent archetypal forces that defined and influenced
human existence according to the celestial movements, and
while the medieval cosmology maintained this same general
structure, reinterpreted according to Christian symbolism,
the modern cosmology posited a planetary Earth in a neutral
infinite space, with a complete elimination of the
traditional celestial-terrestrial dichotomy. The heavenly
bodies were now moved by the same natural and mechanical
forces and composed of the same material substances as those
found on the Earth. With the fall of the geocentric cosmos
and the rise of the mechanistic paradigm, astronomy was
finally severed from astrology. In contrast to both the
ancient and the medieval world views, the celestial bodies
of the modern universe possessed no numinous or symbolic
significance; they did not exist for man, to light his way
or give meaning to his life. They were straightforwardly
material entities whose character and motions were entirely
the product of mechanistic principles having no special
relation either to human existence <p.288> per se or
to any divine reality. All specifically human or personal
qualities formerly attributed to the outer physical world
were now recognized as naive anthropomorphic projections and
deleted from the objective scientific perception. All divine
attributes were similarly recognized as the effect of
primitive superstition and wishful thinking, and were
removed from serious scientific discourse. The universe was
impersonal, not personal; nature’s laws were natural, not
supernatural. The physical world possessed no intrinsic
deeper meaning. It was opaquely material, not the visible
expression of spiritual realities.’
p.288
‘As
the Earth had been removed from the center of creation to
become another planet, so now was man removed from the
center of creation to become another animal.’
p.289
‘The
structure and movement of nature was the result not of God’s
benevolent design and purpose, but of an amoral, random, and
brutal struggle for survival in which success went not to
the virtuous but to the fit. … Humans, animals, plants,
organisms, rocks and mountains, planets and stars, galaxies,
the entire universe could now be understood as the
evolutionary outcome of entirely natural processes. …
The
Christian doctrine of Christ’s divine intervention in human
history—the Incarnation of the Son of God, the Second Adam,
the Virgin Birth, the Resurrection, the Second Coming—seemed
implausible in the context of an otherwise straightforward
survival-oriented Darwinian evolution in a vast mechanistic
Newtonian cosmos.’
p.290
‘The
Christian doctrine of spiritual redemption as based on the
historical manifestation of Christ and his future
apocalyptic Second Coming was first reconceived as
coinciding with the progressive advance of human
civilization under divine providence, conquering evil
through man’s God-given reason, and then was gradually
extinguished altogether in light of the belief that man’s
natural reason and scientific achievements would
progressively realize a secular utopian era marked by peace,
rational wisdom, material prosperity, and human dominion
over nature. The Christian sense of Original Sin, the Fall,
and collective human guilt now receded in favor of an
optimistic affirmation of human self-development and the
eventual triumph of rationality and science over human
ignorance, suffering, and social evils.’ (see p.289 – contradiction)
p.291
‘It
is no small irony that Aristotle, the greatest naturalist
and empirical scientist of antiquity, whose work had served
as the sustaining impulse of Western science for two
millennia, was jettisoned by the new science under the
impetus of a romantic Renaissance Platonism—from Plato, the
speculative idealist who most systematically wished to leave
the world of the senses. But with Aristotle’s transformation
by the contemporary universities into a stultified
dogmatist, the Platonism of the Humanists had succeeded in
opening the scientific imagination to a fresh sense of
intellectual adventure.’
p.291-292
Aristotle
was an ancient empiricist and Plato an ancient rationalist.
The Copernican was based on Plato’s and Pythagoras’s work.
The Sun was thus exalted to God with the
Platonic/Pythagorean influence. The empirical study of the
natural world, being dependent on mathematics also has its
origin in the Platonic/Pythagorean influence. The mystical
Platonic/Pythagorean influence was however excluded by the
empiricist emphasis on the natural world. (see p.291 – contradiction?)
p.294
‘The
ancient birth of astronomy, and of science itself, had been
inextricably tied to the primitive astrological
understanding of the heavens as a superior realm of divine
significance, with the planetary movements carefully
observed because of their symbolic import for human affairs.
In the ensuing centuries, astrology’s ties to astronomy had
been essential for the latter’s technological progress, for
it was the astrological presuppositions that gave astronomy
its social and psychological relevance, as well as its
political and military utility in matters of state. …
…
Copernicus made no distinction in the De Revolutionibus
between astronomy and astrology, referring to them
conjointly as “the head of all the liberal arts.’
p.295-296-297
‘While
the original revolutionaries themselves called no attention
to the problems the new paradigm posed for astrology, those
contradictions soon became apparent for others. For a
planetary Earth seemed to undermine the very foundation
<p.296> of astrological thinking, since the latter
assumed the Earth was the absolute central focus of
planetary influences. It was difficult to see how without
the privileged position of being the fixed universal center,
the Earth could continue to deserve such a distinctive
cosmic attention. … After Galileo and Newton, the
celestial-terrestrial division could no longer be
maintained, and without that primordial dichotomy, the
metaphysical and psychological premises that had helped
support the astrological belief system began to collapse. …
After being the classical “queen of sciences” and the guide
of emperors and kings for the better part of two millennia,
astrology was no longer credible.
…
That the gods were nothing more than colorful figments of
pagan fantasy needed little argument from the Enlightenment
on. Just as the Platonic Forms died out in philosophy, their
place taken by objective empirical qualities, subjective
concepts, cognitive categories, or linguistic “family
resemblances,” so did the ancient gods assume the role of
literary characters, artistic images, useful metaphors
without any claim to ontological reality.
…
Although in fact an astonishing variety of epistemological
sources had converged to make possible the Scientific
Revolution—the immense imaginative (and antiempirical) leap
to the conception of a planetary Earth, (9) Pythagorean and
Neoplatonic aesthetic and mystical <p.297> beliefs,
Descartes’s revelatory dream and vision of a new universal
science and his own mission to forge it, Newton’s
Hermetically inspired concept of gravitational attraction,
all the serendipitous recoveries of the ancient manuscripts
(Lucretius, Archimedes, Sextus Empiricus, the
Neoplatonists), the fundamentally metaphorical character of
the various scientific theories and explanations—these were
all later viewed as significant only in the context of
scientific discovery.
p.298-299-300
‘For
it was the <p.299> Scholastics’ exhaustive examination
and criticism of those ideas, and their creation of new
alternative theories and concepts—rudimentary formulations
of inertia and momentum, the uniform acceleration of freely
falling bodies, hypothetical arguments for a moving
Earth—that allowed modern science from Copernicus and
Galileo onward to begin forging its new paradigm. … Man’s
intellectual relation to the creative Logos, his privileged
possession of the divine light of the active
intellect—Aquinas’s lumen
intellectus agentis—was from the Christian perspective
precisely what mediated the human understanding of the
cosmos.
…
After Bacon, Galileo, Descartes, and Newton, that authority
had been effectively impugned, and Scholasticism’s
reputation never recovered. From then on, science and
philosophy could move forward without theological
justification, without recourse to a divine light in the
human intellect, without the colossal supporting
superstructure of Scholastic metaphysics and epistemology.
…
Yet despite the unambiguously secular character of the
modern science that eventually crystallized out of the
Scientific Revolution, the original scientific
revolutionaries themselves continued to act, think, and
speak of their work in terms conspicuously redolent of
religious illumination. <p.300> … In the De Revolutionibus,
Copernicus celebrated astronomy as a “science more divine
than human,” closest to God in the nobility of its
character, and upheld the heliocentric theory as revealing
the true structural grandeur and precision of God’s cosmos.’
p.301
‘Both Descartes
and Newton constructed their cosmological systems on the
assumption of God’s existence.’
p.303-304
‘What, then,
caused this shift from the explicit religiosity of the
scientific revolutionaries of the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries to the equally emphatic secularism of the Western
intellect in the nineteenth and twentieth? Certainly the
metaphysical incongruity of the two outlooks, the cognitive
dissonance resulting from the attempts to hold together such
innately divergent systems and sensibilities, eventually had
to force the issues in one direction or the other. The
character and the implications of the Christian revelation
simply did not cohere well with those of the scientific
revelation. … <p.304> water from rocks, partings of
seas—all appeared increasingly improbable to the modern
mind, bearing as they did too many similarities to other
mythical or legendary concoctions of the archaic
imagination.’
Reader
postulates currently that the comfort, which the scientific
world caused and the financial security also caused the
split, due to no need for reliance on God. Another cause is
the ‘singularity’ of God of truth, which meant only ‘One’ is
honest. Honesties and truths as logical necessity of science
require a rejection of religion in order to be scientific
and not ‘singular’ God of truth.
p.305
‘With
Luther, the monolithic structure of the medieval Christian
Church had cracked. With Copernicus and Galileo, the
medieval Christian cosmology itself had cracked. With
Darwin, the Christian world view showed signs of collapsing
altogether.’
22 May 2013
p.308
‘In preference
to traditional biblical Christianity, Enlightenment Deists
like Voltaire argued in favor of a “rational religion” or a
“natural religion.” Such would be appropriate not only to
the rational apprehension of nature’s order and the
requirement of a universal first cause, but also to the
West’s encounter with other cultures’ religions and ethical
systems—an encounter suggesting to many the existence of a
universal religious sensibility grounded in common human
experience.’
The above was
already done with the idea that truth is a first principle
of experiments and science.
p.308-309
‘With Descartes,
God’s existence had been affirmed not through faith but
through reason; yet on that basis God’s certain existence
could not be indefinitely sustained, as Hume and Kant, the
culminating philosophers of the Enlightenment, noted in
their different ways. Much as Ockham had warned four
centuries earlier, rational philosophy could <p.309>
not presume to pronounce on matters that so far transcended
the empirically based intellect.’
p.309
‘In the
eighteenth century, Hume and Kant systematically refuted the
unwarrantability of using causal reasoning to move from the
sensible to the supersensible.’
The above is not
true for reader because Kant had a very different view on
causality than Hume. With both Humes’s and Kant’s philosophy
God can be motivated because Hume said that God causes every
single event and Kant said the way to the transcendent is
through physical truths and honesties.
p.309
‘For Kant, God
was an unknowable transcendent—thinkable, not knowable, only
attending to man’s inner sense of moral duty.’
p.310
‘Human history
could be understood as progressing from a mythical and
theological stage, through a metaphysical and abstract
stage, to its final triumph in science, based on the
positive and concrete.’
p.312-313
‘Like his
fellows in the vanguard of the Enlightenment, Rousseau
argued with the weapons of critical reason and reformist
zeal. Yet the progress of civilization they celebrated
seemed to him the source of much of the world’s evil. Man
suffered from the civilization’s corrupt sophistications,
which alienated him from his natural condition of
simplicity, sincerity, equality, kindness, and true
understanding. Moreover, Rousseau believed religion was
intrinsic to the human condition. He contended that the
philosophes’ exaltation of reason had neglected man’s actual
nature—his feelings, his depths of impulse and intuition and
spiritual hunger that transcended all abstract formulae.
Rousseau certainly disbelieved in the organized churches and
clergy, … <p.313> Rousseau believed humanity could
best learn to worship the Creator by turning to nature, for
there lay a sublimity that all could understand and feel. …
The deity recognized by Rousseau was not an impersonal first
cause, but a God of love and beauty whom the human soul
could know from within. Reverent awe before the cosmos, the
joy of meditative solitude, the direct intuitions of the
moral conscience, the natural spontaneity of human
compassion, a “theism of the heart—these constituted the
true nature of religion.
Rousseau
thus set forth an immensely influential position beyond
those of the orthodox Church and the skeptical philosophes,
combining the religiosity of the former with the rational
reformism of the latter, yet critical of both: if the one
was constricting in its narrow dogmatism, the other was
scarcely less so in its arid abstractions. And here lay the
seed for contradictory developments, for at the same time
that Rousseau reaffirmed man’s religious nature, he
encouraged the modern sensibility in its gradual departure
from Christian orthodoxy. He gave a rational reformist’s
support to the lingering religious impulse of the modern
mind, yet he gave that impulse new dimensions that served
the Enlightenment’s undermining of the Christian tradition.
Rousseau’s embrace of a religion whose essence was universal
rather than exclusive, whose ground was in nature and man’s
subjective emotions and mystical intuitions rather than in
biblical revelation, initiated a spiritual current in
Western culture that would lead first to Romanticism and
eventually to the existentialism of a later age.’
Why the tendency
to generalize about finding God in nature or in
transcendence? Why not everywhere by accepting truths as
leading factor? It could be argued according to Clouser’s
philosophy that accepting truths as first principle implies
a reductionist process to truths, but Clouser did it
himself, whilst arguing against reduction. Somewhere it has
to stop? Literal readings of Exodus 20:4 mean no
correspondence is acceptable. False testimony is disallowed
later in Exodus 20. That means only making false predictions
was allowed by the pluralistic God of Genesis.
p.314
‘Despite their
high-minded doctrines, the organized churches seldom seemed
to concern themselves with the plight of workers or the
poor. This seeming contradiction, Marx held, was in fact
essential to the churches’ character, for the true role of
religion was to keep the lower classes in order. … Organized
religion formed an essential element in the bourgeoisie’s
control of society, for religious beliefs lulled the
proletariat into self-defeating inaction.
…
… It
was no longer mandatory in Western society to be Christian,
and in coincidence with this growing freedom, fewer members
of the culture found the Christian belief system
intrinsically compelling or satisfying. Both liberal
utilitarian and radical socialist philosophies seemed to
offer the contemporary age more cogent programs fro human
activity than the traditional religions.’
Self
The above
statement by Tarnas points to utilitarianism at an extreme
side and socialism another side. Intequinism is not between
the two sides. Communism and capitalism has a(n) utilitarian
society therefore the two sides Tarnas sees do not make
sense to reader currently. Capitalism and communism were
partly the same, even though communism destroyed religion.
The two systems distributed the wealths of utilitarianism
differently.
p.316
‘The traditional
image of the Semitic-Augustinian-Protestant God, who creates
man too weak to withstand evil temptation, and who
predestines the majority of his human creatures to eternal
damnation with little consideration of their good works or
honest attempts at virtue, ceased to be either palatable or
plausible to many sensitive members of modern culture.’
p.317
‘In the light of
psychoanalysis, the Judaeo-Christian God could be seen as a
reified psychological projection based on the child’s naive
view of its libidinally restrictive and seemingly omnipotent
parent. Reconceived in this way, many aspects of religious
behavior and belief appeared to be comprehensible as
symptoms of a deeply rooted cultural obsessive-compulsive
neurosis. The projection of a morally authoritative
patriarchal deity could be seen as having been a social
necessity in earlier stages of human development, satisfying
the cultural psyche’s need for a powerful “external” force
to undergird society’s ethical requirements. But having
internalized those requirements, the psychologically mature
individual could recognize the projection for what it was,
and dispense with it.’
p.319
‘The new
psychological constitution of the modern character had been
developing since the high Middle Ages, had conspicuously
emerged in the Renaissance, was sharply clarified and
empowered by the Scientific Revolution, then extended and
solidified in the course of the Enlightenment. By the
nineteenth century, in the wake of the democratic and
industrial revolutions, it had achieved mature form. The
direction and quality of that character reflected a gradual
but finally radical shift of psychological allegiance from
God to man, from dependence to independence, from
otherworldliness to this world, from the transcendent to the
empirical, from myth and belief to reason and fact, from
universals to particulars, from a supernaturally determined
static cosmos to a naturally determined evolving cosmos, and
from a fallen humanity to an advancing one.
p.322
‘The religious
faith in God’s eventual salvation of mankind—whether
Israel’s arrival in the Promised land, the Church’s arrival
at the millennium, the Holy Spirit’s progressive perfecting
of humanity, or the Second Coming of Christ—now became an
evolutionary confidence, or revolutionary belief, in an
eventual this-worldly utopia whose realization would be
expedited by the expert application of human reason to
nature and society.’
23 May 2013
p.326
‘The
peculiar phenomenon of contradictory consequences ensuing
from the same intellectual advance was visible from the
start of the modern era with Copernicus’s dethroning of
the Earth as the center of creation. In the same instant that man
liberated himself from the geocentric illusion of
virtually all previous generations of mankind, he also
effected for himself an unprecedented fundamentally cosmic
displacement. The universe no longer centered on man; his
cosmic position was neither fixed nor absolute. And each
succeeding step in the Scientific Revolution and its
aftermath added new dimensions to the Copernican effect,
further propelling that liberation while intensifying that
displacement.
With
Galileo, Descartes, and Newton, the new science was forged,
a new cosmology defined, a new world opened to man within
which his powerful intelligence could act with new freedom
and effectiveness. Yet simultaneously, that new world was
disenchanted of all those personal and spiritual qualities
that for millennia had given human beings their sense of
cosmic meaning. The new universe was a machine, a
self-contained mechanism of force and matter, devoid of
goals or purpose, bereft of intelligence or consciousness,
its character fundamentally alien to that of man. The
premodern world had been permeated with spiritual, mythic,
theistic, and other humanly meaningful categories, but all
these were regarded by the modern perception as
anthropomorphic projections. Mind and matter, psyche and
world, were separate realities. The scientific liberation
from theological dogma and animistic superstition was thus
accompanied by a new sense of human alienation from a world
that no longer responded to human values, nor offered a
redeeming context within which could be understood the
larger issues of human existence.’
p.327
‘With
the world no longer a divine creation, a certain spiritual
nobility seemed to have departed from it, an impoverishment
that also necessarily touched man, its erstwhile crown. …
Man’s character, his mind and will, came from below, not
above. … Man could now recognize that he rode forth at the
crest of evolution’s advance, nature’s most complex and
dazzling achievement; but he was also just an animal of no
“higher” purpose. … The chief facts of human history until
the present were fortuitously supportive biophysical
circumstances and brute survival, with no apparent larger
meaning or context, and with no cosmic security supplied by
any providential design from above.’
p.328
‘Freud thereby
represented a brilliant culmination of the Enlightenment
project, bringing even the human unconscious under the light
of rational investigation.
Yet
on the other hand, Freud radically undermined the entire
Enlightenment project by his revelation that below or beyond
the rational mind existed an overwhelmingly potent
repository of nonrational forces which did not readily
submit either to rational analysis or to conscious
manipulation, and in comparison with which man’s conscious
ego was a frail and fragile epiphenomenon.’
p.330
Historicism
became a dominant way of explaining new formations with the
philosophies of Darwin, Marx and Freud.
p.331
The
Copernican heliocentric cosmos changed into a much vaster
image with countless stars and constellations where
distances are measured in light years and human significance
diminished exponentially.
p.332
Historicism
expanded to become determinism, which explained that
everything including reason is only results of previous
events.
p.333-334
‘It was above
all John Locke, Newton’s contemporary and Bacon’s heir, who
set the tone for the Enlightenment by affirming the
foundational principle of empiricism: There is nothing in
the intellect that was not previously in the senses (Nihil est in
intellectu quod non antea fuerit in sensu). … The mind
is at first a blank tablet, upon which experience writes.
<p.334> … From those impressions, the mind can build
its conceptual understanding by means of its own
introspective and compounding operations. The mind possesses
innate powers, but not innate ideas. Cognition begins with
sensation.
The
British empiricist demand that sensory experience be the
ultimate source of knowledge of the world set itself in
opposition to the Continental rationalist orientation,
epitomized in Descartes and variously elaborated by Spinoza
and Leibniz, which held that the mind alone, through its
recognition of clear, distinct, and self-evident truths,
could achieve certain knowledge.’
Self
I think Locke
believed in being reborn because of his thoughts about a
blank mind at birth.
p.334-335
Locke identified
objects, appearances in mind, and thinking. He also
distinguished between primary and secondary appearances. A
primary appearance was represented by objective measurement
of devices, using mathematical units. Weight identified, for
example, was a primary appearance in mind. Secondary
appearances in mind related to human senses for example
smelling or seeing, which formed impressions in mind.
Secondary appearances in mind were subjective and primary
appearances in mind objective. Bishop Berkeley then argued
that primary appearances are impressions in mind just as
secondary appearances are in impressions in mind and
therefore all appearances are equally subjective in mind.
Bishop
Berkeley’s argument did not accept the values of mediating
rationalities, which are represented by devices like scales
and descriptive languages like mathematics. The objective
measurement of a wave by a sensor can be standardized with
devices. Standardization can cause mediation and agreement
if production and distribution benefits of devices are
shared in intequible ways.
p.335-336
‘.. Berkeley, a
bishop of the church, sought to overcome the <p.336> contemporary
tendency toward “atheistic Materialism” which he felt had
unjustifiably arisen with modern science. … All that can be
known with certainty to exist is the mind and its ideas,
including those ideas that seem to represent a material
world. From a rigorously philosophical pint of view, “to be”
does not mean “to be a material substance”; rather, “to be”
means “to be perceived by a mind” (esse est percipi).’
It seams
Berkeley meant to be conscious of own actions and body
movements means “to be”. To be conscious of self (soul not
body) is another consciousness, which Berkeley seems not to
have perceived.
p.336
‘Yet Berkeley
held that the individual mind does not subjectively
determine its experience of the world, … the world and its
order depend on a mind that transcends individual minds and
is universal—namely, God’s mind.’
p.337-338
‘To begin his
analysis, Hume made a distinction between sensory
impressions and ideas: Sensory impressions are the basis of
any knowledge, and they come with a force and liveliness
that make them unique. Ideas are faint copies of those
impressions. One can experience through the senses and impression of the
color blue, and on the basis of this impression one can have
an idea of that
color whereby the latter can be recalled. The question
therefore arises, What causes the sensory impression? If every valid
idea has a basis in a corresponding impression, then to what
impression can the mind point for its idea of causality?
None, Hume answered. … The mind draws from its experience an
explanation that in fact derives from the mind itself, not
from the experience. The mind cannot really know what causes
the sensations, for it never experiences “cause” as a
sensation. It experiences only simple impressions, atomized
phenomena, and causality per se is not one of those simple
impressions. … <p.338> It [Cause – own insert] is the
reification of a psychological expectation, apparently
affirmed by experience but never genuinely substantiated.
Hume reified
some “causes” as possible miracles of God, although he
stated “causes” of causes as the unknown, it seems.
p.338
‘Part of Hume’s
intention was to refute the metaphysical claims of
philosophical rationalism and its deductive logic. In Hume’s
view, two kinds of propositions are possible, one based
purely on sensation and the other purely on the intellect. A
proposition based on sensation concerns obvious matters of
concrete fact (e.g., “it is a sunny day”), which are always
contingent (they could have been different, though in fact
they were not). By contrast, a proposition based purely on
intellect concerns relations between concepts (e.g., “all
squares have four equal sides”), and these are always
necessary—that is, their denial leads to self-contradiction.
But the truths of pure reason, such as those of mathematics,
are necessary only because they exist in a self-contained
system with no mandatory reference to the external world. …
Hence the only truths of which pure reason is capable are
tautological. Reason alone cannot assert a truth about the
ultimate nature of things.’
p.339
‘.. for Hume,
metaphysics was just an exalted form of mythology, of no
relevance to the real world.
But
another and, for the modern mind, more disturbing
consequence of Hume’s critical analysis was its apparent
undermining of empirical science itself, for the latter’s
logical foundation, induction, was now recognized as
unjustifiable. The mind’s logical progress from many
particulars to a universal certainty could never be
absolutely legitimated: no matter how many times one
observes a given event-sequence, one can never be certain
that that event-sequence is a causal one and will always
repeat itself in subsequent observations.’
p.340
‘In
the long evolution of the Western mind from the ancient
idealist to the modern empiricist, the basis of reality had
been entirely reversed: Sensory experience, not ideal
apprehension, was the standard of truth—and that truth was
utterly problematic.
…
… But
with the more secular skepticism of Hume, nothing could be
said to be objectively necessary—not God, not order, not
causality, nor substantial existents, nor personal identity,
nor real knowledge. All was contingent. … Thus did Hume
articulate philosophy’s paradigmatic skeptical argument, one
that in turn was to stimulate Immanuel Kant to develop the
central philosophical position of the modern era.’
Although Hume,
according to Tarnas promoted a world without metaphysics, i
read Tarnas’s explanation of Hume as the opposite; as if
Hume motivated God (first mover of Aristotle? In Venter’s
book he elaborated on Hume’s analysis of art, i think with
reference to Aristotle’s mimesis) as causing unknowns, later
explained by Kant as noumena.
p.341
'The intellectual
challenge that faced Kant in the second half of the
eighteenth century was a seemingly impossible one: on the
one hand, to reconcile the claims of science to certain and
genuine knowledge of the world with the claim of philosophy
that experience could
never give rise to such knowledge; on the other hand, to
reconcile the claim of religion that man was morally free
with the claim of science that nature was entirely
determined by necessary laws.
… The mind required empirical evidence before
it could be capable of knowledge, but God, immortality, and
other such metaphysical matters could never become
phenomena; they were not empirical. Metaphysics, therefore,
was beyond the powers of human reason.'
p.342
'Kant
himself had long been convinced that natural science was
scientific to the precise extent that it approximated to the
ideal of mathematics. Indeed, on the basis of such a
conviction, Kant himself had made an important contribution
to Newtonian cosmology, demonstrating that through strictly
necessary measurable physical forces, the Sun and planets
had consolidated and assumed the motions defined by
Copernicus and Kepler.'
'By Hume's reasoning, with which Kant had to agree, the
certain laws of Euclidian geometry could not have been
derived from empirical observation. Yet Newtonian science
was explicitly based upon Euclidian geometry. If the laws of
mathematics and logic were said to come from within the
human mind, how could they be said to pertain with certainty
to the world? Rationalists like Descartes had more or less
simply assumed a mind-world correspondence, but Hume had
subjected that assumption to a damaging critique.'
p.343
'Kant's
extraordinary solution was to propose that the mind-world
correspondence was indeed vindicated in natural science, yet
not in the naive sense previously assumed, but in the
critical sense that the "world" science explicated was a
world already ordered by the mind's own cognitive apparatus.
For in Kant's view, the nature of the human mind is such
that it does not passively receive sense data. … In the act
of human cognition, the mind does not conform to things;
rather, things conform to the mind.'
Self
Geometry is based
on physical, seen objects, for example triangles therefore
it is based on nature, very basic simple nature.
p.343-344
How
did Kant arrive at this epoch-making conclusion? He began by
noting that if all content that could be derived from
experience was withdrawn from mathematical judgments, the
ideas of space and time still remained. From this he
inferred that any event experienced by the senses is located
automatically in a framework of spatial and temporal
relations. …
<p.344>
… Because mathematical propositions are based on direct
intuitions of spatial relations, they are
"a-priori"—constructed by the mind and not derived from
experience—and yet they are also valid for experience, which
will by necessity conform to the a priori form of space. It
is true that pure reason inevitably becomes entangled in
contradiction if it attempts to apply these ideas to the
world as a whole—to ascertain what is true beyond all
possible experience—as trying to decide whether the universe
is infinite or finite either in time or space. But as
regards the phenomenal world that man does experience, time
and space are not just applicable concepts, they are
intrinsic components of all human experience of that world,
frames of reference mandatory for human cognition.'
p.345
'Although Kant
criticized Leibniz and the rationalists for believing that
reason alone without sense experience can calculate the
universe (for, Kant argued, knowledge requires acquaintance
with particulars), he also criticized Locke and the
empiricists for believing that sense impressions alone,
without a priori concepts of the understanding, could ever
lead to knowledge (for particulars are meaningless without
general concepts by which they are interpreted). Locke was
correct to deny innate ideas in the sense of mental
representations of physical reality, but wrong to deny
innate formal knowledge. … Only in conjunction can
understanding and sensibility supply objectively valid
knowledge of things.'
p.346-347
'Man's
knowledge, then does not conform to objects, but objects
conform to man's knowledge. Certain knowledge is possible in
a phenomenal universe because the human mind bestows to that
universe its own absolute order. Thus Kant proclaimed what
has been called his "Copernican revolution": As Copernicus
had explained the perceived movements of the heavens by the
actual movement of the observer, so <p.347> Kant
explained the perceived order of the world by the actual
order of the observer. (1)'
Self
I
recall that in Critique
of pure reason Kant referred to Copernicus in a
derogatory way as if his astronomy was make-belief.
p.489
'(1)
On the basis of Kant's second preface to the Critique of Pure
Reason, it has often been said that Kant called his
insight a "Copernican revolution" (e.g., by Karl Popper,
Bertrand Russel, John Dewey, and the fifteenth edition of
the Ecyclopaedia
Britannica, among many others). I. B. Cohen has
pointed out (in Revolution
in Science [Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1985], 237-243) that Kant does not appear to have made that
specific statement. On the other hand, Kant explicitly
compared his new philosophical strategy to Copernicus's
astronomical theory, and although strictly speaking the term
"Copernican revolution" may postdate both Copernicus and
Kant, both the term and the comparison are accurate and
illuminating.'
p.348-349
'Man knows, as
indeed Aquinas and Aristotle had said, because he judges
things through the medium of a priori principles; but man
cannot know whether these internal principles possess any
ultimate relevance to the real world, or to any absolute
truth or being outside the human mind. … For the modern
mind, the inevitable outcome of a critical rationalism and a
critical empiricism was a Kantian subjectivism limited to
the phenomenal world: Man had no necessary insight into the
transcendent, nor into the world as such. … In
retrospect, the long-term consequences of both the
Copernican and the Kantian revolutions were fundamentally
ambiguous, at once liberating and diminishing. Both
revolutions awakened man to a new, more adventurous
reality, yet both also radically displaced man—one form
the center of the cosmos, the other from genuine cognition
of that cosmos. Cosmological alienation was thereby
compounded by epistemological alienation.
It
could be said that in one sense Kant reversed the Copernican
revolution, since he placed man again at the center of his
universe by virtue of the human mind's central role in
establishing the world order. …
<p.349>
… Man was again at the center of his universe, but this was
now only his
universe, not the
universe.'
Self
Currently i
describe phenomena as objective realities due to possible
agreement amongst people about those realities and to
metaphysical matters i refer to as subjective realities
because of the difficulty in agreeing about noumena and
definitions of God.
p.349-350
'For Kant's
revolution had two sides to it, one focused on science, the
other on religion: he wished to rescue both certain
knowledge and moral freedom, both his belief in Newton and
his belief in God. On the one hand, by demonstrating the
necessity of the mind's a priori forms and categories, Kant
sought to confirm the validity of science. On the other
hand, by demonstrating that man can know only phenomena, not
things in themselves, he sought to make room for the truths
of religious belief and moral doctrine.
… , Kant argued that his limitation of
science's competence to the phenomenal, his recognition of
man's ignorance concerning things in themselves, opened up
the possibility of faith. …
Kant thus held that although one could not know
that God exists, one must nevertheless believe he exists
in order to act morally. … With the
advances of scientific and philosophical knowledge, the
modern mind could no longer base religion on a <p.
350> cosmological or metaphysical foundation, but
instead it could base religion in the structure of the
human situation—and it was through this decisive insight
that Kant, following the spirit of Rousseau and of Luther
before him, defined the direction of modern religious
thought. …
… Here the Humean and Newtonian influences in
Kant's philosophical development were countered by the
universal humanitarian moral ideals of Rousseau, who had
stressed the priority of feeling over reason in religious
experience, and whose works had made a considerable
impression on Kant, reinforcing the deeper roots of Kant's
sense of moral duty coming from his strict Pietist
childhood.'
Self
Charles Taylor and
Richard Tarnas opined that Kant followed Rousseau's spirit.
In my 3rd History of contemporary/modern
philosophy (FILM 878) assignment submitted to Prof. Heyns, i
disagreed with their opinion. The difference between Kant
and Rousseau was also highlighted in Accounting of ideas
submitted to Journal
of philosophy and to Phronimon. Last
year i highlighted the difference in a History of philosophy
(PHIL212) assignment, if i remember correctly.
p.350
'It is clear that
at heart, Kant believed that the laws moving the planets and
stars ultimately stood in some fundamental harmonious
relation to the moral imperatives he experienced within
himself: "Tow things fill the heart with ever new and always
increasing awe and admiration: the starry heavens above me
and the moral law within me."
p.351
'Kant's
penetrating critique had effectively pulled the rug out from
under the human mind's pretensions to a certain knowledge of
things in themselves, eliminating in principle any human
cognition of the ground of the world. Subsequent
developments in the Western mind—the deepening relativisms
introduced not only by Einstein, Bohr … and a host of
others—radically magnified that effect, altogether
eliminating the grounds for subjective certainty still felt
by Kant. … In the wake of Kant's Copernican revolution,
science, religion, and philosophy all had to find their own
bases for affirmation, for none could claim a priori access
to the universe's intrinsic nature.'
24 May 2013
p.351
'The course of
modern philosophy unfolded under the impact of Kant's
epochal distinctions. At first, Kant's successors in Germany
pursued his thinking in an unexpectedly idealist direction.
In the Romantic climate of European culture in the late
eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, Fichte,
Schelling, and Hegel suggested that the cognitive categories
of the human mind were in some sense the ontological
categories of the universe—i.e., that Human knowledge did
not point to a divine reality but was itself that
reality—and on that basis constructed a metaphysical system
with a universal Mind revealing itself through man.'
Self
Still the One,
outside of humanity, but did that One or Absolute of Hegel
have only one representative amongst humans or more than
one?
p.352
'.. because
materialism, or at least naturalism—the position holding
that all phenomena could ultimately be explained by natural
causes—appeared most congruent with the scientific account
of the world, it constituted a more compelling conceptual
framework than did idealism.'
p.353
'In the end, the
human mind could not be relied upon as an accurate judge of
reality. The original Cartesian certainty, that which served
as foundation for the modern confidence in human reason, was
no longer defensible.
Henceforth, philosophy concerned itself largely
with the clarification of epistemological problems, with the
analysis of language, with philosophy of science, or with
phenomenological and existentialist analyses of human
experience. Despite the incongruence of aims and
predispositions among the various schools of
twentieth-century philosophy, there was general agreement on
one crucial point: the impossibility of apprehending an
objective cosmic order with the human intelligence.'
p.355
'With both
philosophy and religion in such problematic condition, it
was science alone that seemed to rescue the modern mind from
pervasive uncertainty. Science achieved a golden age in the
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, with extraordinary
advances in all its major branches, with widespread
institutional and academic organization of research, and
with practical applications rapidly proliferating on the
basis of a systematic linkage of science of technology.'
Self
Thus, truths
progressed with correspondences being common enough to
advance science.
p.355-356-357
'But two
developments in the course of the twentieth century
radically changed science's cognitive and cultural status,
one theoretical and internal to science, the other pragmatic
and external.
… In the first instance, the classical
Cartesian-Newtonian cosmology gradually and then
dramatically broke down … Maxwell's .. Michelson-Morley ..
Becquerel's discovery of radioactivity .. Planck's isolation
of quantum phenomena and Einstein's special and general
theories of relativity, and culminating in the 1920s with
the formulation of quantum mechanics by Bohr, Heisenberg,
and their colleagues, the long-established certainties of
classical modern science were radically <p.356>
undermined. …
…
The planets moved in their orbits not because they were
pulled toward the Sun by an attractive force acting at a
distance, but because the very space in which they moved was
curved. … The uncertainty principle radically undermined and
replaced strict Newtonian determinism. …
…
<p.357> Matter's former hard substantiality had given
way to a reality perhaps more conducive to a spiritual
interpretation. … The deep
interconnectedness of phenomena encouraged a new holistic
thinking about the world, with many social, moral, and
religious implications. … The reductionist program, dominant
since Descartes, now appeared to many to be myopically
selective, and likely to miss that which was most
significant in the nature of things.
… Nevertheless, many felt that the old
materialistic world view had been irrevocably challenged,
and that the new scientific models of reality offered
possible opportunities for a fundamental rapprochement with
man's humanistic aspirations.'
p.358-359
'Yet
these ambiguous possibilities were countered by other, more
disturbing factors. … objects that were not really things at
all but processes or patterns of relationships; phenomena
that took no decisive shape until observed; particles that
seemed to affect each other at a distance with no known
causal link; the existence of fundamental fluctuations of
energy in a total vacuum.
…
Thus in certain respects the intellectual contradictions and
obscurities of the new physics only heightened the sense of
human relativity and alienation growing since the Copernican
revolution. … <p.359> Philosophy's conclusion was
becoming science's as well: Reality may not be structured in
any way the human mind can objectively discern. Thus
incoherence, unintelligibility, and an insecure relativism
compounded the earlier modern predicament of human
alienation in an impersonal cosmos.'
⌘⌘⌘
p.359
'The
fundamental Kantian a prioris—space, time, substance,
causality—were no longer applicable to all phenomena. The
scientific knowledge that had seemed after Newton to be
universal and absolute had to be recognized after Einstein,
Bohr, and Heisenberg as limited and provisional. So too did
quantum mechanics reveal in unexpected fashion the radical
validity of Kant's thesis that the nature described by
physics was not nature in itself but man's relation to
nature—i.e. nature as exposed to man's form of questioning.'
p.360-361
'.. while Popper maintained the rationality of
science by upholding its fundamental commitment to rigorous
testing of theories, its fearless neutrality in the quest
for truth, Kuhn's analysis of the history of science tended
to undercut even that security. … To an extent never
consciously recognized by scientists, the nature of
scientific practice makes its governing paradigm
self-validating. …
<p.361> Kuhn further argued that when the
gradual accumulation of conflicting data finally produces a
paradigm crisis and a new imaginative synthesis eventually
wins scientific favor, the process by which that revolution
takes place is far from rational. It depends as much on the
established customs of the scientific community, on
aesthetic, psychological, and sociological factors, on the
presence of contemporary root metaphors and popular
analogies, on unpredictable imaginative leaps and "gestalt
switches," even on the aging and dying of conservative
scientists, as on disinterested tests and arguments. … Each
paradigm creates its own gestalt, so comprehensive that
scientists working within different paradigms seem to be
living in different worlds. … Whereas Popper had attempted
to temper Hume's skepticism by demonstrating the rationality
of choosing the most rigorously tested conjecture, Kuhn's
analysis served to restore that skepticism.'
⌘⌘⌘
p.362
'As early as the
nineteenth century, Emerson had warned that man's technical
achievements might not be unequivocally in his own best
interests: "Things are in the saddle and ride mankind.'
p.365
'The West was
again losing its faith, this time not in religion but in
science and in the autonomous human reason.
Science was still valued, in many respects
still revered. But it had lost its untainted image as
humanity's liberator.'
p.366
'To be sure, the
Romantic temperament shared much with its Enlightenment
opposite, and their complex interplay could be said to
constitute the modern sensibility. Both tended to be
"humanist" in their high estimate of man's powers and their
concern with man's perspective on the universe.'
p.367
'Whereas the
Enlightenment temperament's high valuation of man rested on
his unequaled rational intellect and its power to comprehend
and exploit the laws of nature, the Romantic valued man
rather for his imaginative and spiritual aspirations, his
emotional depths, his artistic creativity and powers of
individual self-expression and self-creation. …
Whereas for the Enlightenment-scientific mind,
nature was an object for observation and experiment,
theoretical explanation and technological manipulation, for
the Romantic, by contrast, nature was a live vessel of
spirit, a translucent source of mystery and revelation.'
p.368
'Truth discovered
in divergent perspectives was valued above the monolithic
and univocal ideal of empirical science. For the Romantic,
reality was symbolically resonant through and through, and
was therefore fundamentally multivalent, a constantly
changing complex of many leveled meanings, even opposites.'
p.371
'And so the limits
of knowledge established by Locke, Hume, and the positivist
side of Kant were boldly defied by the Idealists and
Romantics of the post-Enlightenment.'
p.374-375
'As time passed,
what had been the medieval dichotomy between reason and
faith, which was followed by the early modern dichotomy
between secular science and the Christian religion, now
became a more general schism between scientific rationalism
on the one hand and the multifaceted Romantic humanistic
culture on the other, with the latter now including a
diversity of religious and philosophical perspectives
loosely allied with the literary and artistic tradition.'
p.376
'The faith-reason
division of the medieval era and the religion-science
division of the early modern era had become one of
subject-object, inner-outer, man-world, humanities-science.
A new form of the double-truth universe was now
established.'
p.376
'In
the longer run, however, the early Romantic sense of harmony
with nature underwent a distinct transformation as the
modern era grew old. Here the Romantic temperament was
complexly influenced by its own internal developments, by
the sundering effects of modern industrial civilization and
modern history, and by science's view of nature as
impersonal, non-anthropocentric, and random.'
p.379
'At the foundation
of Hegel's thought was his understanding of dialectic,
according to which all things unfold in a continuing
evolutionary process whereby every state of being inevitably
brings forth its opposite. The interaction between these
opposites then generates a third stage in which the
opposites are integrated—they are at once overcome and
fulfilled—in a richer and higher synthesis, which in turn
becomes the basis for another dialectical process of
opposition and synthesis. (5) …
…
… While Kant had argued that reason could not
penetrate the veil of phenomena to reach the ultimate
reality, since man's finite reason inevitably became caught
in contradiction whenever it attempted to do so, Hegel saw
human reason as fundamentally an expression of a universal
Spirit or Mind (Geist),
through the power of which, as in love, all opposites could
be transcended in a higher synthesis.'
p.380
'Whereas for Plato
the immanent and secular was ontologically dismissed in
favor of the transcendent and spiritual, for Hegel this
world was the very condition of the Absolute's
self-realization. In Hegel's conception, both nature and
history are ever progressing toward the Absolute: The
universal Spirit expresses itself in space as nature, in
time as history.'
p.381
'Just as it was
only through the experience of alienation from God that man
could experience the joy and triumph of rediscovering his
own divinity, so it was only through the process of God's
becoming finite, in nature and in man, that God's infinite
nature could be expressed. For this reason, Hegel declared
that the essence of his philosophical conception was
expressed in the Christian revelation of God's incarnation
as man, the climax of religious truth.
… Man is not the passive spectator of reality,
but its active co-creator, his history the matrix of its
fulfillment. The universal essence, which constitutes and
permeates all things, finally comes to consciousness of
itself in man.
… Hegel's influence was considerable, first in
Germany and later in English-speaking countries, encouraging
a renascence of classical and historical studies from an
Idealist perspective and providing a metaphysical bulwark
for spiritually disposed intellectuals grappling with the
forces of secular materialism. A new attentiveness to
history and to the evolution of ideas was thereby
engendered, with history seen as motivated ultimately not
simply by political or economic or biological—i.e.,
material—factors, though these all played a role, but rather
by consciousness itself, by spirit or mind, by the
self-unfoldment of thought and the power of ideas.'
p.382
'His abstract
metaphysical certitudes seemed to avoid the grim reality of
death, and to disregard the human experience of God's
remoteness and inscrutability.'
p.385
'In the course of
analyzing a vast range of psychological and cultural
phenomena, found evidence of a collective unconscious common
to all human beings and structured accordingly to powerful
archetypal principles.'
p.385
'A new dimension
to Hegel's understanding of historical dialectic emerged
with Jung's insight into the collective psyche's tendency to
constellate archetypal oppositions in history before moving
toward a synthesis in a higher level.'
p.387
'.. depth
psychology ..'
p.388
'Just as man had
become a meaningless speck in the modern universe, so had
individual persons become insignificant ciphers in modern
states, to be manipulated or coerced by the millions.'
27 May 2013
p.395
'Each
great epochal transformation in the history of the Western
mind appears to have been initiated by a kind of archetypal
sacrifice. … suffered at the birth of the postmodern by
Nietzsche, who signed his last letters "The Crucified," and
who died at the dawn of the twentieth century.'
'There is an
appreciation of the plasticity and constant change of
reality and knowledge, a stress on the priority of concrete
experience over fixed abstract principles, and a conviction
that no single a priori thought system should govern belief
or investigation.'
p.396
'Reality
is not a solid, self-contained given but a fluid, unfolding
process, an "open universe", continually affected and molded
by one's actions and beliefs. … The knowing subject is never
disengaged from the body or from the world, which form the
background and conditions of every cognitive act.
… The mind is not the passive reflector of an
external world and its intrinsic order, but is active and
creative in the process of perception and cognition. Reality
is in some sense constructed by the mind, not simply
perceived by it, and many such constructions are possible,
none necessarily sovereign.'
28 May 2013
p.400
'The most
prominent philosophical outcome of these several converging
strands of postmodern thought has been a many-sided critical
attack on the central Western philosophical tradition from
Platonism onward. The whole project of that tradition to
grasp and articulate a foundational Reality has been
criticized as a futile exercise in linguistic game playing,
a sustained but doomed effort to move elaborate fictions of
its own creation. More pointedly, such a project has been
condemned as inherently alienating and oppressively
hierarchical—an intellectually imperious procedure that has
produced an existential and cultural impoverishment, and
that has led ultimately to the technocratic domination of
nature and the social-political domination of others. The
Western mind's overriding compulsion to impose some form of
totalizing reason—theological, scientific, economic—on every
aspect of life is accused of being not only self-deceptive
but destructive.'
p.401
'"… To think well,
to feel well, to act well, to read well, according to the épistème of
unmaking, is to refuse the tyranny of wholes; totalization
in any human endeavor is potentially totalitarian."(8) …
Properly speaking, therefore, there is no
"postmodern world view," nor the possibility of one.'
p.490
'8.
Ihab Hassan, quoted in Albrecht Wellmer, "On the
Dialectic of Modernism and Postmodernism," Praxis International
4 (1985): 338. See also Richard J. Bernstein's discussion of
the same passage in his 1988 Presidential Address to the
Metaphysical Society of America ("Metaphysics, Critique,
Utopia, " Review of
Metaphysics 42 [1988]: 259-260), where he
characterizes the postmodern intellectual attitude as
sometimes resembling Hegel's description of a
self-fulfilling abstract skepticism, "which only ever sees
pure nothingness in its result … [and] cannot get any
further from there, but must wait to see whether something
new comes along and what it is, in order to throw it too
into the same empty abyss" (G,W.F. Hegel, The Phenomenology
of Spirit, translated by A.V. Miller [Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1977], 51).'
p.402
'Everything could
change tomorrow. Implicitly, the one postmodern absolute is
critical consciousness, which, by deconstructing all, seems
compelled by its own logic to do so to itself as well. This
is the unstable paradox that permeates the postmodern mind.'
⌘⌘⌘
p.404
'The postmodern collapse of meaning has thus
been countered by an emerging awareness of the individual's
self-responsibility and capacity for creative innovation and
self-transformation in his or her existential and spiritual
response to life.'
p.405
'Imagination is no longer conceived as
simplistically opposed to perception and reason; rather,
perception and reason are recognized as being always
informed by the imagination. With this awareness of the
fundamental mediating role of the imagination in human
experience has also come an increased appreciation of the
power and complexity of the unconscious, as well as new
insight into the nature of archetypal pattern and meaning.
The postmodern philosopher's recognition of the inherently
metaphorical nature of philosophical and scientific
statements (Feyerabend, Barbour, Rorty) has been both
affirmed and more precisely articulated with the postmodern
psychologist's insight into the archetypal categories of the
unconscious that condition and structure human experience
and cognition (Jung, Hillman). The long-standing
philosophical problem of universals, which had been partly
illuminated by Wittgenstein's concept of "family
resemblances"—his thesis that what appears to be a definite
commonality shared by all instances covered by a single
general word in fact often comprises a whole range of
indefinite, overlapping similarities and relationships—has
been given new intelligibility through depth psychology's
understanding of archetypes.'
p.408
Feminism has made significant inroads.
⌘⌘⌘
p.409
'The postmodern era is an era without consensus
on the nature of reality, but it is blessed with an
unprecedented wealth of perspectives with which to engage
the great issues that confront it.'
p.410
'The intellectual question that looms over our
time is whether the current state of profound metaphysical
and epistemological irresolution is something that will
continue indefinitely, taking perhaps more viable, or more
radically disorienting, forms as the years and decades pass;
whether it is in fact the entropic prelude to some kind of
apocalyptic denouement of history; or whether it represents
an epochal transition to another era altogether, bringing a
new form of civilization and a new world view with
principles and ideals fundamentally different from those
that have impelled the modern world through its dramatic
trajectory.'
p.411
"'Turning
and turning in the widening gyre
The
falcon cannot hear the falconer;
Things
fall apart; the centre cannot hold;
Mere
anarchy is loosed upon the world. …
Surely
some revelation is at hand.
William Butler Yeats
"The Second Coming"'"
p.411-412
'Nietzsche,
in whom "nihilism became conscious for the first time"
(Camus), who had foreseen the cataclysm that would befall
European civilization in the twentieth <p.412>
century, realized within himself the epochal crisis that
would finally come when the modern mind became conscious of
its destruction of the metaphysical world, "the death of
God":
'"What
were we doing when we unchained this earth from its sun?
Whither is it moving now? Whither are we moving? Away from
all suns? Are we not plunging continually? Backward,
sideward, forward, in all directions? Is there still any up
or down? Are we not straying as through an infinite nothing?
Do we not feel the breath of empty space? Has it not become
colder? Is not night continually closing in on us? (10)"'
p.490
'10.
Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, translated by
W. Kaufman (New York: Random House, 1974), 181.'
p.412
'"Only a god can save us," said Heidegger at
the end of his life. And Jung, at the end of his, comparing
our age to the beginning of the Christian era two millennia
ago, wrote: '… … [own abstract of Tarnas's quote follows]
Does the individual know that he is the makeweight that tips
the scales? (12)'
p.490
'12.
Carl G. Jung, "The Undiscovered Self," in Collected Works of Carl
Gustav Jung, vol. 10, translated by R.F.C. Hull,
edited by H. Read et al. (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1970), pars. 585-586.'
p.413
'If ever boldness, depth, and clarity of vision
were called for, from many, it is now. Yet perhaps it is
this very necessity that could summon forth from us the
courage and imagination we now require.'
22
June 2013
p444
'I
believe that the West's restless inner development and
incessantly innovative masculine ordering of reality has
been gradually leading, in an immensely long dialectical
movement, toward a reconciliation with the lost feminine
unity, toward a profound and many-leveled marriage of the
masculine and feminine, a triumphant and healing reunion.'
P445
'Today
we are experiencing something that looks very much like the
death of modern man, indeed that looks very much like the
death of Western man. Perhaps the end of "man" himself is at
hand. But man is not a goal. Man is something that must be
overcome—and fulfilled, in the embrace of the feminine.'
13 June 2013
P469
'When major thinkers and writers of
the past used the word "man" or other masculine generics to
indicate the human species—as, for example, in The Descent of Man
(Darwin, 1871), or De
hominis dignitate oratio ("Orations on the Dignity of
Man," Pico della Mirandolo, 1486), or Das Seelenproblem des
modernen Menschen ("The Spiritual Problem of Modern
Man," Jung, 1928)—the meaning of the term was pervaded by
fundamental ambiguity. It is usually clear that a writer who
employed such an expression in this kind of context intended
to personify the entire human species, not only members of
the male sex. Yet it is also evident from the larger
framework of understanding within which the word appears
that such a term was generally intended to denote and
connote a decisively masculine contour in what the writer
understood to be the essential nature of the human being and
the human enterprise. This shifting but persistent ambiguity
of diction—both
gender-inclusive and
masculine-oriented—must be accurately conveyed if one is
to understand the distinctive character of Western cultural
and intellectual history. The implicit masculine meaning of
such terms was not accidental, even if it was largely
unconscious. If the present narrative were to attempt to
convey the mainstream traditional Western image of the human
enterprise by systematically and unvaryingly using
gender-neutral expressions such as "humankind," "humanity,"
"people," "persons," "women and men," and "the human being"
(along with "she or he" and "his or her"), instead of what
would actually have been used—man, anthrōpos, andres,
homines, der Mensch, etc.—the result would be roughly
comparable to the work of a medieval historian who, when
writing about the ancient Greek view of the divine,
consciously substituted the word "God" every time the Greeks
would have said "the gods," thereby correcting a usage that
to medieval ears would have seemed both wrong and
offensive."
[1]
P472: 'From this important fragment from
Xenophanes, W.K.C. Guthrie states: "The emphasis on
personal search, and on the need for time, marks this as
the first statement in extant Greek literature of the
idea of progress in the arts and sciences, a progress
dependent on human effort and not—or at least not
primarily—on divine revelation" (A History of Greek
Philosophy, vol. 1, The Earlier Presocratics and the
Pythagoreans [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1962], 399-400).'
[2]
P472: 'The evolution of the Greek view of human
history and of the human relation to the divine can be
discerned in the shifting nature and status of the
mythological Prometheus. Hesiod's earlier depiction of
Prometheus as the trickster who stole fire from Olympus
for mankind against Zeus's wishes was greatly expanded
by Aeschylus in Prometheus
Bound, whose titanic protagonist gave mankind all
the arts of civilization and thereby brought it from a
state of primitive savagery to intellectual mastery and
dominion over nature. Hesiod's seriocomic figure became
for Aeschylus a tragic hero of universal stature; and
while Hesiod had viewed human history as an inevitable
regress from an aboriginal golden age, Aeschylus's
Prometheus celebrated mankind's progress to
civilization. … While it is difficult to ascertain
Aeschylus's precise view of the myth's ontological
significance, it would seem that he conceived of
Prometheus and man in essentially mythopoeic terms as a
symbolic unity.
… See E.R. Dodds,
"Progress in Classical Antiquity," in Dictionary of the
History of Ideas, edited by Philip P. Weiner (New
York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1973) 3: 623-626.'
[3]
P472-473: Tarnas referred here to other works in
which explanations were given about Plato's explanations
of connections between irrationality and femininity;
rationality and male sexuality. He also refers to
homoeroticism in Plato's works especially in Symposium.
Tarnas wrote that Vlastos wrote that Plato wrote in the
climactic argument of Symposium how
'.. a homosexual paradigm changes to a procreative
heterosexual one when Diotima describes the highest
fulfillment of Eros as the philosopher's conjugal union
with the Idea of Beauty, which brings forth the birth of
wisdom.'
[4]
Pagina 474: 'The philosophical integration of
Hellenism with Judaism was initiated by Philo of
Alexandria (b.c. 15-10 B.C.), who identified the Logos
in Platonic terms as the Idea of Ideas, as the summation
of all Ideas, and as the source of the world's
intelligibility; and in Judaic terms as God's
providential ordering of the universe and as mediator
between God and man. The Logos was thus both the agent
of creation and the agent by which God was experienced
and understood by man. Philo taught that the Ideas were
God's eternal thoughts, which he created as real beings
prior to the creation of the world. Later Christians
held Philo in high regard for his views of the Logos,
which he called the first-begotten Son of God, the man
of God, and the image of God. Philo appears to have been
the first person to have attempted to integrate
revelation and philosophy, faith and reason—the basic
impulse of Scholasticism. Little recognized in Judaic
thought, he had a marked influence on Neoplatonism and
medieval Christian theology.'
[5]
P475: 'Enchiridion, in Augustine, Works, vol. 9,
edited by M. Dods (Edinburgh: Clark, 1871-77), 180-181.'
[6]
P484: 'Ockham himself used formulations, somewhat
different from that now known as Ockham's razor, such as
"Plurality is not to be assumed without necessity" and
"What can be done with fewer [assumptions] is done in
vain with more." '
[7]
p484: 'Translated by Mary Martin McLaughlin in
The Portable Renaissance Reader, edited by J.B. Ross and
M.M. McLaughlin (New York: Penguin, 1977), 478.'