Important: If you reached this web page via a link,
other than to the Home page, you must go to the Home
page to acknowledge the rules of the domain.
Back
to Unedited Philosophy Quotes and Ramblings about Intequinism.
Book title: The gay science (Die vrolike wetenskap)
Author: Friedrich Nietzsche
Translator: Walter Kaufmann
Publisher: Vintage Books (A division of Random
House)
Place: New York
Date: March 1974
Reader: Mr. M.D. Pienaar
3 August 2014
"BOOK FIVE – WE
FEARLESS ONES" (Nietzsche, 1974:277)
"Section 344 – How we, too, are still
pious" (Nietzsche, 1974:280)
'We see that science
also rests on a faith; there simply is no science "without
presuppositions." The question whether truth is needed
must not only have been affirmed in advance, but affirmed to
such a degree that the principle, the faith, the conviction
finds expression: "Nothing
is needed more
than truth, and in relation to it everything else has only
second-rate value."
This unconditional
will to truth—what is it? Is it the will not to allow oneself to
be deceived? Or is it the will not to deceive?'
(Nietzsche, 1974:281)
'Section 357 – On the old problem:
"What is German?"' (Nietzsche, 1974:304)
'You see what it was
that really triumphed over the Christian god: Christian
morality itself, the concept of truthfulness that was
understood ever more rigorously, the father confessor's
refinement of the Christian conscience, translated and
sublimated into a scientific conscience, into intellectual
cleanliness at any price. … interpreting one's own
experiences as pious people have long enough interpreted
theirs, as if everything were providential, a hint, designed
and ordained for the sake of the salvation of the soul—that
is all over now,
that has man's concscience against it, that is
considered indecent and dishonest by every more refined
conscience—mendaciousness, feminism, weakness, and
cowardice. In this severity, if anywhere, we are good Europeans and
heirs of Europe's longest and most courageous
self-overcoming.' (Nietzsche, 1974:307)
12 April 2015
Section "325
What belongs to greatness.--Who will attain anything great if he does not
find in himself the strength and the will to inflict great
suffering? Being able to suffer is the least thing; weak
women and even slaves often achieve virtuosity in that. But
not to perish of internal distress and uncertainty when one
inflicts great suffering and hears the cry of this
suffering--that is great, that belongs to greatness.[1]"
(Nietzsche, 1974:255)
This statement by
Nietzsche, i think, should be understood as merely a
reflection of truth. Read together with the section where he
said that not one has ever had the courage to let everything
go, it means that Nietzsche had not admiration for
"greatness". I think he indicated that foul play caused
material wealth for self and misery for others, just as a
matter of fact. The way i understand Nietzsche is that he
did not necessarily promote "greatness", he just stated it
as fact and actually opposed the type of behaviour, which
cause "greatness". This section about "greatness" can be
understood together with Foucault statement at the end of Madness and
Civilization, where Foucault stated that wealth is
dependent on the misery of others currently. Foucault stated
that the 'greatness' we see in the world is dependent on
misery. Without the misery, the 'greatness' cannot exist.
That makes sense if understood in the context of Accounting of ideas,
and actions of the Caiaphaci. At section 311, which Kaufmann
compares Nietzsche states that his misery, which is caused
by "greatness" actually enforces Nietzsche's truthfull life,
which cause misery, but which he regards not as miserable.
It is a statement by a type of Cynic, comparable to
Diogenes's (of Sinope) way of life. It means to keep ones'
dignity in the sphere of being 'sacrificed'.
At section 326
Nietzsche seems to act like Socrates who said the
un-investigated life is not worth living. (NIetzsche,
1974:256) Could he have really transcended into a type of
blissfulness in his pain? It seems it is possible if the
Stoics and the Cynics endured more pain than for example
Nietzsche and still decided not to complain. Nietzsche took
a stoic stance.
15 April 2015
Section "344
How we, too, are still pious.-- In science convictions have no rights of
citizenship, as one says with good reason. Only when they
decide to descend to the modesty of hypotheses, of a
provisional experimental point of view, of a regulative
fashion, they may be granted admission and even a certain
value in the realm of knowledge--though always with the
restriction that they remain under policy supervision, under
the police of mistrust. --But does this not mean, if you
consider it more precisely, that a conviction may obtain
admission to science only when it ceases to be a conviction?
Would it not be the first step in the discipline of the
scientific spirit that one would not permit oneself any more
convictions?
Probably this is so;
only we still have to ask: To make it possible for
this discipline to begin, must there not be some prior
conviction--even one that is so commanding and unconditional
that it sacrifices all other convictions to itself? We see
that science also rests on a faith; there simply is no
science "without presuppositions." The question whether truth is needed
must not only have been confirmed in advance, but affirmed
to such a degree that the principle, the faith, the
conviction finds expression: "Nothing is needed
more than truth, and in relation to it everything else has
only second-rate value."
This unconditional
will to truth--what is it? Is it the will not to allow oneself to
be deceived? Or is it the will not to deceive? For
the will to truth could be interpreted in the second way
too--if only the special case "I do not want to deceive
myself" is subsumed under the generalization "I do not want
to deceive." But why not deceive? But why not allow oneself
to be deceived?
Note that the
reasons for the former principle belong to an altogether
different realm from those for the second. One does not want
to allow oneself to be deceived because one assumes that it
is harmful, dangerous, calamitous to be deceived. In this
sense, science would be a long-range prudence, a caution, a
utility; but one could object in all fairness; How is that?
Is wanting not to allow oneself to be deceived really less
harmful, less dangerous, less calamitous? What do you know
in advance of the character of existence to be able to
decide whether the greater advantage is on the side of the
unconditionally mistrustful or of the unconditionally
trusting? But if both should be required, much trust as well as much
mistrust, from where would science then be permitted to take
its unconditional faith or conviction on which it rests,
that truth is more important than any thing, including every
other conviction? Precisely this conviction could never have
come into being if both truth and untruth constantly proved
to be useful, which is the case. Thus--the faith in science,
which after all exists undeniably, cannot owe its origin to
such a calculus of utility; it must have originated in spite of the
fact that the disutility and dangerousness of "the will to
truth," of "truth at any price" is proved to it constantly.
"At any price": how well we understand these words once we
have offered and slaughtered one faith after another on this
altar!
Concequently, "will
to truth" does not
mean "I will not allow myself to be deceived" but--there is
no alternative--"I will not deceive, not even myself"; and with that we stand
on moral ground. For you only have to ask yourself
carefully, "Why do you not want to deceive?" especially if
it should seem--and it does seem!--as if life aimed at
semblance, meaning, error, deception, simulation, delusion,
self-delusion, and when the great sweep of life has actually
always shown itself to be on the side of the most
unscrupulous polytropoi.[2]
Charitably interpreted, such a resolve might perhaps be a
quixotism[3],
a minor slightly mad enthusiasm; but it might also be
something more serious.--"Will to truth"--that might be a
concealed will to death.
Thus the question
"Why science?" leads back to the moral problem: Why have morality at
all when life, nature, and history are "not moral"? No
doubt, those who are truthful in that audacious and ultimate
sense that is presupposed by the faith in science thus affirm another
world than the world of life, nature, and history; and
insofar as they affirm this "other world"--look, must they
not by the same token negate its counterpart, this world, our world?--But
you will have gathered what I am driving at, namely, that it
is still a metaphysical
faith upon which our faith in science rests--that even
we seekers after knowledge today, we godless
anti-metaphysicians still take our fire, too, from the flame
lit by a faith that is thousands of years old, that
Christian faith which was also the faith of Plato, that God
is the truth, that truth is divine.--But what if this should
become more and more incredible, if nothing should prove to
be divine and more unless it were error, blindness, the
lie--if God himself should prove to be our most enduring
lie?--" (Nietzsche, 1974:280-283)
LIST OF REFERENCES
NIETZSCHE, F. 1974. The gay science. (New York:
Vintage Books)
[1] "Cf. section 311 above, especially the
beginning. The distress that this section caused some of
Nietzsche's first readers illustrates his point. He knew
how his development and books had pained his mother and
sister, Richard and Cosima Wagner. Wagner's admirers,
and ever so many others." (Comment by Kaufmann,
Nietzsche, 1974:255)
[2] According to Kaufmann, Nietzsche used this
word to refer to Odysseus, who, thanks to his deceit
survived many ordeals. (Nietzsche, 1974: 282)
[3] According to Kaufmann, Nietzsche
like Don Quixote. (Nietzsche, 1974: 282)